Heidegger was interested in psychiatry, especially with schizophrenics, with whom he sought contact and conversations when this was possible for him. On walks he regularly remained standing lost in thought for a while before the villa of the Freiburg psychiatrist Ruffin [...]. Once he said forthrightly that he was not convinced of the correctness of the solely medical interpretation of schizophrenia as illness. Could it not even simply be a question of an ‘other’ kind of thinking?
Wiesenhütter, E. Die Begegnung zwischen Philosophie und Tiefenpsychologie.
(1979: 158,
translation by A. Stadlen)
What did Martin Heidegger mean? What Eckart Wiesenhütter says he said (above), three years after Heidegger’s death, is ambiguous. The words ‘solely’ (‘allein’) and ‘simply’ (‘einfach’) in the last two sentences suggest two possible ways of understanding ‘schizophrenia’, the second more radical than the first.
Even if Heidegger did have the temerity to suggest the second, more radical, possibility on that one occasion, he was usually careful to explain that what he endorsed was the first possibility. He did revere as ‘an “other” kind of thinking’ what were generally regarded as the ‘maddest’ writings of Hölderlin, Nietzsche, Trakl, Celan; but he tended to emphasise that the ‘medical interpretation’ that they were ‘ill’ was ‘correct’. For example, he called Paul Celan ‘sick’. He did, however, insist that the ‘madman’ in Georg Trakl’s poetry was not ‘mentally ill’.
Of course, when Heidegger used the word ‘correct’, he usually meant wrong, in the light of his more profound understanding. But he still meant ‘correct’! How, though, did he know that the medical diagnosis was correct? He was not a doctor. But he deferred as a layman to the medical ‘expertise’ of such psychiatrists as Ludwig Binswanger and, especially, his friend Medard Boss.
In the 1960s, the decade of the Zollikon seminars, the psychiatrists Thomas Szasz in the United States and R. D. Laing and Aaron Esterson in the United Kingdom were also seriously questioning the foundations of psychiatry. Laing and Esterson endorsed much of Boss’s work while deploring Boss’s ‘recklessness’ (Laing) and ‘lack of clarity’ (Esterson). Szasz criticised Boss’s claim to be available 24 hours a day to a patient as a ‘sham’. The crucial difference was that Szasz, Laing and Esterson questioned the presumption of illness.
Szasz, in The Myth of Mental Illness (1961), The Manufacture of Madness (1970), and many other books and papers, compared the presumption of illness to the presumption of guilt in inquisitorial legal systems. He held, on both scientific and ethical grounds, that people should be presumed healthy until proven ill, just as they are presumed innocent until proven guilty in accusatorial legal systems. He argued that both the presumption of illness and the presumption of guilt invalidate people.
However, the presumption of illness differs from the presumption of guilt in a fundamental way. The presumption of guilt at least attributes agency and responsibility; indeed, it insists on it. But the presumption of illness, and especially ‘mental illness’, attributes lack of agency and responsibility: it literally invalidates by treating the person as an invalid.
A further twist, however, to the attribution of ‘mental illness’, often made nowadays with the insistence that it should be regarded as ‘an illness like any other’, and that it should be given ‘parity of esteem’ with physical illness, is precisely that this alleged ‘illness’ is not treated as an ‘illness like any other’. ‘Mental illness’, unlike physical illness, is taken as a legal justification both for compulsory psychiatry - coercing the innocent - and for the insanity defence - excusing the guilty.
Szasz was as committed as Heidegger and Boss were to holistic medicine. He was no dualist. His first papers and first book Pain and Pleasure were on psychosomatic medicine, and he stood by them at the end of his life more than half a century later, seeing this as an important field wide open for research. But he pointed out that illness (disease) still has first to be established by a natural-scientific criterion such as Virchow’s, of cellular pathology or pathophysiology. A ‘holistic approach to illness’, he insisted, makes no sense if there is no illness to approach. Holistic (or any other kind of) medicine should not betray the ancient principle ‘First do no harm’ by making the presumption of illness.
Laing and Esterson, in Sanity, Madness and the Family (1964), and Esterson, in The Leaves of Spring (1970), demonstrated in concrete detail how, in each of eleven families in which a daughter had been medically diagnosed as ‘schizophrenic’, the presumption by the other family members that this young woman was ‘ill’ served to mystify her and invalidate her experience. Some of the diagnosed women fluctuated between accepting and challenging the family’s and the psychiatrists’ (not, of course, Laing’s or Esterson’s) definition of them as ‘ill’. Others simply accepted, in a defeated and demoralised way, that they were ‘ill’.
Laing and Esterson emphasised in the preface to the second edition of their book that readers had ignored their question, namely (1970 [1964]: viii):
Are the experience and behaviour that psychiatrists take as [boldface added] signs and symptoms of schizophrenia more socially intelligible than has come to be supposed?
They were questioning the existence of ‘schizophrenia’. But for more than half a century they have been misread as if they had left out the seven words here in boldface.
This is not an obscure detail. It is the heart of their argument. But it is so simple that almost all readers manage not to see it.
Indeed, most ‘readers’ acknowledge that they skip the Prefaces and Introduction and do not even see Laing and Esterson’s question, let alone see the point of the words here printed in boldface. Even within the chapters proper, with their readable transcriptions of family conversations and interactions, ‘readers’ ‘read’ the first section of each chapter, ‘Clinical Perspective’, as if this were the authors’ perspective. But the whole point of the book is to contrast the ‘Clinical Perspective’ section with ‘The Family Situation’ section in each of the eleven chapters. ‘The Family Situation’ exemplifies the authors’ own social-phenomenological perspective.
We believe that the shift of point of view that these descriptions both embody and demand has a historical significance no less radical than the shift from a demonological to a clinical viewpoint three hundred years ago.
No one can deny us the right to disbelieve in the fact of schizophrenia.
For example, Emmy van Deurzen and Raymond Kenward assert in their influential Dictionary of Existential Psychotherapy and Counselling (2005: 118):
Laing […] believed schizophrenia was the result of the alienating power of the schizophrenogenic family.
This is what almost all the few existential therapists and Daseinsanalysts who claim to have looked at the book say Laing and Esterson were saying. They are supported in this belief by van Deurzen and Kenward’s statement (2005: 118):
[...] Laing’s overall conceptualisation of his patients was deterministic.
This has been disproved in detail by Anthony Stadlen in ‘Laing in a Lexicon’ (Existential Analysis, 18.2; 2007: 341-5). [See:
In two series of Inner Circle Seminars on the eleven families, for the 40th and 50th anniversaries of the book, we have seen how difficult it is for existential therapists, perhaps because their careers depend on it, to examine their belief in ‘mental health’, ‘mental illness’, and ‘schizophrenia’. Daseinsanalysts have expressed similar puzzlement. But for the ‘laywoman’ Dame Hilary Mantel, the great writer who introduced our second series of seminars, the phenomenological point was obvious. [See:
- Hilary Mantel. Introductions to the families in Laing and Esterson’s Sanity, Madness and the Family in Inner Circle Seminars conducted by Anthony Stadlen (2014-2019)
- ‘The simple words the people speak’: An introduction to Hilary Mantel’s introduction to her and Anthony Stadlen’s (2014) 50th-anniversary Inner Circle Seminar on ‘Maya Abbott and the Abbotts’ in Laing and Esterson’s Sanity, Madness and the Family (1964) (January 2015) ]
Of course, as Szasz pointed out, it is possible that some persons now diagnosed as ‘schizophrenic’ are indeed ill: they may have an undiscovered brain abnormality. If such an abnormality were discovered then it would constitute a bona fide disease with mental symptoms: the province of neurologists.
But often, as Esterson says in Families, Breakdown and Psychiatry (1976: 296),
Such was the hypnotic effect of the prior assumption of illness, that one had constantly to remind oneself that there was no evidence to substantiate this assumption.And (302):
[…] study the designated schizophrenic directly in his relevant social context in a phenomenologically and dialectically valid manner, and to a significant extent the apparent signs and symptoms of the presumed illness disappear like morning mist before the sun […]
[…] with no single patient can one speak of his being schizophrenic per se. Rather, one must always ask: schizophrenic under the excessive demands of what pattern of human relationships?
Professor Miles Groth will participate in the afternoon of this first seminar in this subseries. He is a Daseinsanalyst who has practised since 1975; Professor Emeritus in Psychology at Wagner College, Staten Island, New York City; translator of Heidegger; author of books and papers on Heidegger and Boss, including Medard Boss and the Promise of Therapy (2020); collaborator with Todd DuBose in The Soul of Existential Therapy (2020) and a Society for Existential Analysis symposium in November 2020.
Professor Keith Hoeller and Dr Albert Pacheco will join Anthony Stadlen in conducting another seminar in this subseries (date to be announced).
Professor Hoeller co-conducted (by Zoom from Seattle, heroically through the night) Inner Circle Seminars No. 258 (The Myth of ‘Thomas Szasz’) on 14 June 2020 and No. 259 (Heidegger and Levinas on the ‘Holy’) on 2 August 2020.
Dr Albert Pacheco is Director of Behavioral Health Services for South Central Family Health Services in Los Angeles, CA. He has over 20 years of clinical experience. His doctoral dissertation, based on the work of Medard Boss, was reviewed and approved by Boss himself, and he has discussed with both Boss and Szasz their positions on ‘mental illness’. He has published articles on Boss and existential psychology and is an editorial board member of the Review of Existential Psychology and Psychiatry, which published (!) his important paper The Myth of Existential Psychiatry. He is completing a book, An Introduction to the Existential Psychology of Medard Boss.
These will be online seminars, using Zoom.
No comments:
Post a Comment