The Madhouse of Being
Anthony Stadlen
Copyright © Anthony Stadlen 2007, 2020
[Daseinsanalyse 23 (2007): 94-135.]
[Daseinsanalyse 23 (2007): 94-135.]
[Existential Analysis 18.1 (January 2007): 117-154.]
[The Existential Analysis version does not include the long endnote 176 (included here) of the Daseinsanalyse version, which was published as a separate article, ‘“Laing” in a Lexicon: Was R. D. Laing “deterministic”?’, in Existential Analysis 18.2 (July 2007): 341-347, also published separately on this blogsite:
‘Laing’ in a Lexicon: Was R. D. Laing ‘deterministic’? (July 2007).]
(This is the edited and expanded version of an unscripted lecture on the second day, Friday 26 May 2006, of the 6th Forum of the International Federation of Daseinsanalysis, held on the theme ‘Speech in Daseinsanalysis – A Dialogue of Philosophy and Psychotherapy in Practice’ in Prague from 25–27 May 2006.)
‘Laing’ in a Lexicon: Was R. D. Laing ‘deterministic’? (July 2007).]
(This is the edited and expanded version of an unscripted lecture on the second day, Friday 26 May 2006, of the 6th Forum of the International Federation of Daseinsanalysis, held on the theme ‘Speech in Daseinsanalysis – A Dialogue of Philosophy and Psychotherapy in Practice’ in Prague from 25–27 May 2006.)
Many of the
beautiful lectures we have been listening to, on speech and language in
Daseinsanalysis, have referred to the primordial documents of our history. For
example, the word of God, at the beginning. In Hebrew[1]:
vay’omer ’elohim yehi ’or. vayehi ’or.
(And God said:
‘Let there be light.’ And there was light.)
And, as the Czech language makes clear, there is an intimate
relation between light and world. Light is světlo,
world is svět. And there is nothing
like language for lighting up the world – or for darkening, obscuring, making
the world a hell-hole.
So language can be, and is, ‘the house of Being’[2], in Heidegger’s ‘makeshift’[3] phrase. But we mortals are also able to construct and maintain language as a
madhouse of Being. This is my theme today.
2
The very first
two-way conversation in the Bible is not between two human beings. It’s not
between God and man. It’s between the serpent and Eve. This is the first conversation
of which we hear two sides. And the serpent seduces Eve by language.
The serpent says[4]:
‘Yea,
hath God said: Ye shall not eat of any tree of the garden?’
Now, Eve knows, or at least she’s heard from Adam, that that’s not
quite what God said. But the serpent has muddled up the syntax of what God had
said. God had said[5]:
‘Of every tree of
the garden thou mayest freely eat; but of the tree of the knowledge of good and
evil, thou shalt not eat of it; for in the day that thou eatest thereof thou shalt
surely die.’
Eve knows there’s something wrong somewhere, but she can’t quite
place it. The serpent has already disorientated her. So she makes a mistake
when retelling what she has heard God has said. She says[6]:
‘Of the fruit of
the trees of the garden we may eat; but of the fruit of the tree which is in
the midst of the garden, God hath said: Ye shall not eat of it, neither shall
ye touch it, lest ye die.’
Now God had never said they mustn’t touch the tree. So the serpent
has created a ‘false memory’ by his subtle method of seduction. Eve does not
accept the serpent’s version outright, but he has induced her to collude with
his insinuation by ‘remembering’ God’s prohibition as more severe than it in
fact was.[7]
Even more subtle is the serpent’s inducing Eve to transform God’s
moral warning, ‘thou shalt surely die’, into ‘lest ye die’, a mere statement of
mechanistic causality.[8]
The first two-way conversation between two humans in the Bible comes at a rather surprising place. A lot has
happened: the expulsion from Eden, Cain and Abel, Noah’s flood, the tower of Babel … There have been many generations
of men and women before we hear two sides of a human conversation. This first
two-way human conversation is between Abram, who has not yet become Abraham,
and the king of Sodom .
Abram has defeated the armies of four kings led by Chedorlaomer,
king of Elam .
The king of Sodom
clambers out of the slime-pit[9]
into which he has fallen while fleeing from Chedorlaomer, and tries to seduce
Abram, saying[10]:
‘Give me the
persons [the prisoners of war], and take the goods to thyself.’
But Abram, in a magnificent refusal, says[11]:
‘I have lifted up
my hand unto the LORD, God Most High, Maker of heaven and earth, that I will
not take a thread nor a shoe-latchet nor aught that is thine, lest thou
shouldest say: “I have made Abram rich”.’
These two two-way conversations in the Bible[12],
the first of all, between the serpent and Eve, and then the first two-sided human conversation, between Abram and
the king of Sodom ,
are extremely subtle and deep and complex conversations. They are already
conversations about conversations,
purported past and imagined future. They include a great deal of the mystery of
language. They show its possibility for seduction and mystification. But they
also show the heroism and grandeur of Abram’s refusal. He sees the false
position that the king of Sodom is trying to put
him into, and anticipates, in quotation marks as it were, what the king of Sodom would say were he to
succeed in seducing Abram.
3
Now, I want to
resume a discussion from the last two daseinsanalytic Fora, in Zürich in 1999[13]
and Vienna in
2003[14].
I shall present a short excerpt from a recording to illustrate Heidegger’s
notion that ‘die Sprache spricht’,
‘language speaks’.[15]
On 21 April 2006 ,
the pianist and conductor Daniel Barenboim gave a BBC Reith Lecture[16]
in Berlin .
Afterwards there were questions. In the audience was Sir Peter Jonas, the
director of the Munich
opera.
PETER JONAS: Peter Jonas from
the Munich
opera…
SUE LAWLEY: Who we should
probably say used to run the English National Opera too.
PETER JONAS: There are about
twenty questions I would like to ask, but –
SUE LAWLEY: Could you just
ask one –
DANIEL BARENBOIM: Start with the
nineteenth –
PETER JONAS: I’m only going
to ask one. And it seems to me that the words lack of understanding and
incomprehensibility between nations, between beliefs, is a constant theme here,
also in relation to Munich .
After all – [quickly, correcting himself] music. – After all, [audience
laughter begins] when – [Audience
laughter increases.]
DANIEL BARENBOIM: [Laughing loudly.] Ha, ha, ha,
ha, ha, ha – [Crescendo of audience
laughter; applause.] What was his name? Siegmund Freud. No? [Laughter of Sue Lawley, Peter Jonas,
audience.]
PETER JONAS: When we are
born, we are lifted up by our feet, and the first thing that comes out is not a
fully formed sentence, or a political speech, it is a cry, a scream, a sound,
which is very akin to singing, and it seems to me that people can sing before
they can form logical sentences without even Freudian slips. [Slight laughter of Sue Lawley and audience.]
Is it your belief that the magic of music could be more than just an aid to
understanding, that it could be an Esperanto for future communication?
DANIEL BARENBOIM: Well, there has
to be a real revolution in that, I think, because I’m rather disturbed very
often by the concept of communication. Musicians today more and more are
actually communicators, who happen to be musicians, and they use music to
communicate. And that the real communication of music comes when music is the
communication itself.
In this excerpt there are several points relevant to our Forum.
Heidegger shared Daniel Barenboim’s distrust of ‘communication’, and
would surely have agreed that ‘the real communication of music comes when music
is the communication itself.’
One does not have to lift a newborn baby by its feet. But it is
often done, and the baby is routinely measured so. Peter Jonas’s vivid
description makes clear that the baby’s first cry is not just a reflex, but a response, to what is being done to it.[17]
Heidegger in his winter 1928–29 Freiburg lectures insists that this ‘crying, wriggling moving
into the world’ (‘Schreien, zappelnde
Bewegung in die Welt’) shows that the baby is not a ‘shut-in subject’: ‘it
is already out there with…’ (‘es ist
schon draußen bei…’).[18]
Then there is
Peter Jonas’s ‘Freudian slip’: ‘Munich ’
instead of ‘music’. How are such ‘slips’ to be understood in Daseinsanalysis?
To
recapitulate:
Freud gives a
hostage to fortune in the section on slips in his Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis. He says[21]
that ‘the perceived phenomena (die wahrgenommenen Phänomene) must give way to the merely
assumed strivings (die nur angenommenen
Strebungen)’. Binswanger cites[22]
this sentence in his lecture for Freud’s eightieth birthday. In the ‘Ellen
West’ case he calls[23]
it the ‘fundamental principle (Grundsatz)
of psychoanalysis’. Binswanger, Boss, Condrau, the British psychotherapist
Cohn, and Heidegger, on at least twenty-nine occasions[24],
allege that, since Freud has stated this so-called ‘Grundsatz’, it follows that psychoanalysis is not phenomenological.
But Freud’s
reference to ‘merely assumed strivings’ is ambiguous. Binswanger et al. exploit its ambiguity while
praising what they call its exemplary clarity. They claim that Freud means
occult, hypothetical, non-human ‘strivings’ in a reified ‘unconscious’.
In the Zollikon seminars of 24 and 28 January
1964, the first in Boss’s house that were transcribed, Heidegger alleges[25]:
…in
Freud’s treatise on the faulty actions [parapraxes or mischievements] such
suppositions are the strivings [Strebungen] and forces [Kräfte]. These assumed
strivings and forces cause and produce the phenomena.
Freud’s only ‘treatise’ on the ‘faulty actions’ is The
Psychopathology of Everyday Life, referred
to as such by Freud himself[26].
But the word ‘Strebungen’ does not
appear in it[27]. ‘Strebung’
appears just once[28],
in a footnote[29]
added by Freud in 1924 to this work published in 1901, but it is
phenomenological, from his own memories of childhood, not mechanistic. So
Heidegger appears to be pronouncing on a book he has not read.
His reference
to ‘assumed strivings [Strebungen]’ indicates
that he is, like the other authors I have mentioned, thinking of the ‘Grundsatz’, from the Introductory Lectures.
None of these
authors is phenomenological enough to mention the context of Freud’s remark.
The context is
Freud’s discussion of slips or ‘mischievements’[30].
He is reserving the right to see meaning in a slip of the tongue even though
the speaker denies it.[31]
Thus
Daseinsanalysis defines itself in the
first instance by its difference with psychoanalysis in the field of language.
But is Freud
not justified? If we listen in a more generous, more truly daseinsanalytic way,
can we not hear that, in a ‘Freudian slip’, language
speaks, whether the speaker admit it or no?[32]
Should not Daseinsanalysts be attuned to this phenomenon?
That language
speaks cannot be shown by natural science. But is it not often shown, in the
first instance, by laughter, provided this is backed by evidence?
To see this,
let us start with an example where the speaker does not deny that his ‘slip’ has meaning. Does not the laughter of
Daniel Barenboim and his audience have its own validity, quite apart from Peter
Jonas’s implicit ‘admission’?
We must be
careful, however. Laughter may be based on a wrong assumption. But, even if
those laughing ‘merely assume’, as Freud puts it, that Jonas’s ‘slip’ has a
background in, for example, the local politics of the Munich opera, this
assumption is still not an inference about occult ‘forces’, even if it happens
to be wrong. The ‘Strebungen’ Freud
refers to are human ‘strivings’.[33]
They are in principle open to everyone to see and hear, though they may be
hidden or unknown, and though people may dispute what they have seen and heard,
and what it means, as they always have done. This background is the human
context. It is phenomenological, not ‘metapsychological’.
But it is important to do more than ‘merely assume’. To learn about
the human context of Peter Jonas’s ‘slip’, I telephoned him in Munich . To my
astonishment, he told me[34]
that his ‘slip’ had been ‘rigged’. The programme-makers had suggested that a ‘slip’
might ‘break the ice’. Barenboim and Lawley had expected him to ask that
question, and to make some sort of ‘slip’, though they had not known what
‘slip’.
I asked Jonas why he thought the audience would
find his ‘slip’ funny. He said that the Berliners, who spoke good English,
would laugh that Jonas of the Munich opera took
‘Munich ’ to
mean ‘music’. Munich sees itself as the cultural
and musical capital, indeed the
capital, of Germany .
Berlin finds
this amusing. The ‘slip’ might not have worked in any other location in the
world.
Jonas was simulating
a ‘Freudian slip’. Like Shakespeare[35],
Schiller[36],
Tolstoy[37],
Joyce[38],
Mann[39],
Beckett[40],
and Nabokov[41],
he invented one. Unlike them, he pretended not to be pretending. But his
invention, like theirs, still serves to show how language speaks.
What if the speaker does deny that his slip has meaning? Freud
‘assumed’ he had to go ‘behind’ the ‘perceived phenomena’. But language speaks
whether we admit it or not.
In a conversation with Boss on 29 January 1964 , after the
seminar, Heidegger discusses[42] the ambiguity of ‘Annahme’ (‘assumption’). ‘Annahme’,
like ‘assumption’, can mean ‘suppositio’
(‘supposition’; e.g., of a supposed
cause). But it can also mean ‘acceptio’
(‘acceptance’; e.g., of responsibility,
or of luggage at a check-in [Gepäckannahme]).
Heidegger summarises (my translation):
Acceptio: it reveals
itself from out of itself [sie weist sich
von sich aus aus], proves itself itself [beweist sich selbst]. Suppositio: can not be
revealed [kann nicht ausgewiesen werden],
but it gets proved [aber es wird bewiesen].
Heidegger speaks also of the ambiguity of ‘sich versprechen’. With ‘sich’ accusative, it means ‘to make a
slip of the tongue’. With ‘sich’
dative, it means ‘to promise (to) oneself’, or ‘to expect’, as in Heidegger’s
example, ‘Ich verspreche mir nichts von
diesem Auto’ (‘This car doesn’t show any promise’, ‘I don’t expect anything
from this car’). ‘Versprechen’ means
‘to promise’ or ‘a promise’. ‘Versprecher’
is a ‘slip of the tongue’.
We may say:
I honour, or keep faith with, my promise by
keeping my word (by my action). My
action completes my stated intention.
I ‘honour’, or keep faith with, my slip by
‘keeping’ my word (as my action). My acknowledged
intention completes my action.
I honour both my promise and my slip by assuming
responsibility.
In both promise and slip there is what Freud
called ‘Nachträglichkeit’[43]
(deferral, supplementarity, ‘afterwardsness’).
I make a slip: ich verspreche mich (accusative): I promise myself
(to myself and others).
It slipped out. I
was not in it, I shall come later. As Freud says[44]:
‘Where It was, shall [or should] I come to be’ (‘Wo Es war, soll Ich werden’).
I may have a responsibility to accept or assume another’s slip as a ‘Freudian slip’ even if he denies it.
On 2 August 1969 , Heidegger sent Boss a note[45]. In it, he affirmed
Freud’s concept of ‘repression’; but as ‘an ecstatic-intentional
world-relationship to things, living beings and fellow human beings’, not as
the outcome of ‘a psychical mechanics or dynamics’.
Boss wrote[46]:
Freud
abandoned his central aim and violated his own brilliant innovation of seeing
human phenomena in a meaningful historical perspective when he interpolated assumed processes. [My emphasis.]
But Daseinsanalysts all too often abandon a meaningful historical
perspective by failing to assume (in Heidegger’s sense) the other’s actions as praxis (in Sartre’s sense).
Boss does,
when it suits him, choose to see slips as ‘Freudian’. Meerwein
writes[47]
that ‘in psychoanalysis the interest in the assumed strivings must recede
behind that in the perceived phenomena’; thus Meerwein appears ‘inadvertently’
to invert Freud’s ‘Grundsatz’. Boss
calls[48]
Meerwein’s mistake a ‘fundamental mischievement [Fehlhandlung]’.
Boss appears to hold Meerwein responsible for this alleged ‘Fehlhandlung’. But elsewhere, discussing
‘so-called “repression into the unconscious”’, he argues (my translation)[49]:
[…] the
‘having-to-look-away’ […] is quite other than a free and autonomously decided
action. On the contrary, it is a matter of ‘not-being-able-to-do-otherwise’,
and indeed in consequence of a dictatorship of the mentality of early
upbringing-persons.
This sounds
like Freud’s ‘psychic determinism’[50].
But Freud was at least inconsistent. On the one hand, he argued that Luther’s
reported words, ‘Here I stand: I can do no other’, proved ‘determinism’;
although their moral force (if Luther did say them) derives from their
implication, ‘not that he was afflicted with a general paralysis’, as Antony
Flew put it[51],
but that he could indeed do other, by going against his conscience. Freud’s
confusion has led to one kind of decadent ‘Freudianism’. But on the other hand,
as Heaton has pointed out[52],
Freud in practice ‘took a moral
stance towards’ slips. ‘He enlarged the realm of moral discourse, he altered
what we regard as reasonable and excusable.’
Boss does not
appear interested in helping people assume responsibility for their slips. He
does say[53]
that, through Daseinsanalysis, a ‘former patient’ may ‘attune himself’ to ‘Gelassenheit [releasedness, serenity]
towards things and openness for the mystery’, as enjoined by Heidegger in his
1955 Messkirch speech, ‘Gelassenheit’[54].
If this means that the ‘patient’ now assumes responsibility for his slips, Boss
does not say so. Perhaps we are to take it that he who has reached ‘Gelassenheit’ is beyond making slips.
Condrau writes of a psychology student who spoke of having
congratulated his sister on her ‘Verwählung’
(‘misdialling’) when he ‘meant’ to say ‘Vermählung’
(‘wedding’).[55] The
student said he approved of his sister’s choice. How, he asked, could this be a
‘Freudian’ slip? Condrau asks, what right do we have to say it is? And he is
right. But that is because we do not know the student. It might be that those
who knew him and his sister and her new husband would have burst into
spontaneous laughter.
Condrau says[56]
he is approaching slips as Daseinsanalysis approaches dreams. But what he says
about the student’s slip is at odds with what he says about dreams[57]:
If we did, indeed,
base our thinking on the idea that the dreamer decides on the meaning of
his/her dream, this would open the doors wide to a subjectivistic
phenomenology.
This is the authentic daseinsanalytic approach. Boss, in his first
book on dreams (1953), also denies that ‘the dreamer decides on the meaning of
his/her dream’. He asks[58]: ‘Or are there perhaps in reality no dream symbols at all?’ He
insists that the dreamer of the ‘strange dream of an urn’, who interprets the
urn as a ‘symbol’, is wrong.
A dream is private, though its telling is not. But a slip is often
public. Does not Condrau’s point about the meaning of dreams hold a fortiori for the meaning of slips?
How do we, how should we, decide whether a phrase is a slip; and, if so, whether it is a
‘Freudian’ slip; and, if so, what it may mean? Surely, in each case, we look,
or should look, at the social-phenomenological background, the human context.
The context may seem so obvious that we may laugh, as at a joke, though we may
be mistaken. Or the context may seem obscure. Either way, it calls for
exploration.
For example, the musicologist Maynard Solomon thought[59] that Beethoven had made
[…] a clear
mental error – what Freud’s translators used to call a ‘parapraxis’ or
‘symptomatic action’. […] On a leaf of
sketches dated late September 1815 Beethoven addressed himself to God:
‘Almighty in the forest! I am happy, blissful in the forest! Every tree speaks
through Thee [jeder Baum spricht durch Dich].’ Surely, I thought, Beethoven meant
to say, ‘Thou speakest through every tree.’
But Solomon
found other writings of Beethoven’s, including a note from 1815 or 1816[60]:
‘It is indeed,’
he wrote in stammering phrases, ‘as if every tree in the countryside spoke to
me [als ob jeder Baum zu mir spräche],
saying “Holy! Holy!”’
And, some years
later, after finding similar language in Schiller, Novalis, Tieck, Schlegel and
Hölderlin, Solomon reflected:[61]
What had appeared
to be a curious personal image, an idiosyncratic phrase, or even a slip of the
pen, turned out to be a sign of Beethoven’s kinship with wider cultural and
philosophical currents; a simple metaphor opens on a network of shared beliefs
and patterns of thought.
Again, on 5
September 1998 , under the headline ‘At last, Clinton says sorry for affair’, President
Clinton was quoted[62] as saying:
‘There is nothing
that […] anyone else could say in a personally
critical way that I don’t imagine I would disagree with [sic], since I’ve already said it myself to myself. And I’m very
sorry about it. But there’s nothing else I can say.’
The President’s
triple negative appears to gainsay his professed repentance. But further data
would be needed to disprove it.
Daseinsanalysts, who rightly reject
‘metapsychology’, all too often ignore, or distort, social-phenomenological
background too.[63] Uta Jaenicke’s paper ‘Der Biss der Muse’[64]
at our last Forum was a rare exception.
Freud tells in three of his works[65] how the President of the Lower House of the Austrian Parliament
once made a slip. In his first account[66] of the incident, in The
Psychopathology of Everyday Life (1901), Freud explicitly retells the story
already retold by Meringer[67] a year earlier in the Neue
Freie Presse. Meringer was himself reminding readers of a recent public
event. As Freud quotes Meringer[68]:
‘You probably
still recall the way in which the President of the Lower House of the Austrian
Parliament opened the sitting a short
while ago: “High House! I take notice of the presence of so and so many
gentlemen and herewith declare the sitting closed!”
The general merriment [Heiterkeit; my emphasis] made him
notice his mistake and he corrected it. In the present case the explanation is
no doubt that the President wished he was already in the position to
close the sitting, from which little good was to be expected, but – a common
occurrence – the secondary theme at least partly asserted itself and the result
was ‘closed’ for ‘open’, thus the opposite of what was meant to be spoken […]’
Boss and Condrau retell the story, again and again, but censor its
social context.[69]
They do not mention the Austrian Parliament. The Lower House becomes
an anonymous ‘Versammlung’, which
could be a private club. From Boss and Condrau we learn only that Freud told the story and, on the basis
of his ‘metapsychology’ of ‘merely assumed’ intrapsychic forces, suggested that
the President wished to close the meeting. We could not guess that Meringer had told the story and,
invoking merriment not
metapsychology, had suggested that the President wished to close it. Boss and Condrau mention neither Meringer nor
merriment. Their accounts are abstract, stripped of content and context.
What has happened to the quest for ‘the things themselves’?
Boss
and Holzhey-Kunz write[70]: ‘Daseinsanalysis itself
wants to be nothing other than a purified psychoanalysis.’ But it is ‘impure
reflection’[71]
(Sartre) that is abstract. Purifying lets language speak in lucid detail of our
Mitsein, our concrete
being-in-the-world-with-others.
It
is hard work.
In the first two chapters of The
Psychopathology of Everyday Life Freud gives complex analyses of two slips
of memory. In the first, he claims that he forgot the name ‘Signorelli’[72];
in the second, that a ‘young man’ forgot the word ‘aliquis’ in a line of Virgil[73].
He calls both slips ‘paradigms of name-forgetting’[74].
But this is itself a slip, since ‘aliquis’
is not a name but an indefinite pronoun. Is this third slip also ‘Freudian’?
How could one answer this question without exploring the social
background of the two ‘paradigms’? Peter Swales, Richard Skues and I have been
doing so for decades.[75]
Freud claims that the ‘young man’ forgot ‘aliquis’
because he feared he had made his mistress pregnant. But our research shows that
it is more likely that Freud himself
forgot ‘aliquis’, in conversation or
thought, and was worried that he
might have made his wife’s sister Minna Bernays pregnant.
Freud claimed[76]
a special value for his analysis because,
he alleged, a person other than
himself forgot ‘aliquis’. Kurt
Eissler, Director of the Freud Archives, argued[77]
that, since for Freud to lie about this would be ‘impermissable’ [sic] and ‘indecent’, therefore Freud must be telling the
truth.[78]
Most authorities on Freud insist, in addition, that he would never have had a
sexual relationship with Minna.[79]
But in August 2006, thirty years after Swales hypothesised that
Freud’s relationship with Minna was encrypted in the ‘aliquis’ analysis, Franz Maciejewski inspected an old guestbook of
the Hotel Schweizerhaus in Maloja. Freud had sent his wife Martha a postcard
from Maloja dated 13 August
1898 saying that he and Minna were staying ‘in einem bescheidenen [modest] Schweizer
Haus’.[80] In
Freud’s handwriting, an entry in the hotel guestbook on 13 August 1898, the day
he sent his wife the postcard, announced that the guests in Room 11 were ‘Dr Sigm Freud u Frau / Wien’ (‘Dr Sigm
Freud and wife / Vienna’).[81]
Perhaps Freud was short of money (though the Schweizerhaus was
hardly ‘modest’[82])?
Perhaps he would risk sharing a room with Minna only if their relationship was
not sexual? Perhaps he reckoned that
people would reckon that he would
risk sharing a room with Minna only if their relationship was not sexual?[83]
He loved the joke[84]
about the Jew who, according to his interlocutor, is lying because he says he
is going to Cracow to suggest he is going to
Lemberg when in fact he is going to Cracow .[85]
But was the ‘aliquis’
slip, whether fact or fiction, a ‘Freudian slip’ at all? No, says the
philologist Sebastiano Timpanaro.[86]
What, after all, was the slip? Freud claims an Austrian Jew in 1900 has
forgotten the ‘aliquis’ in Virgil’s
line[87],
Exoriare aliquis nostris ex ossibus ultor
(‘Let someone arise from my bones as an avenger’ or ‘Arise from my bones,
avenger, whoever you may be’.) This, says Timpanaro, is normal banalisation[88]:
[…] the uniqueness of the construction in
Latin combined with its odd sound to a German, to make the young Austrian
commit a stylistic and syntactic banalization […] If we suppress exoriare, or nostris ossibus or ultor,
the line loses all its sense; if we suppress aliquis, however, the line is certainly damaged metrically and
aesthetically, but it still has a meaning, particularly in regard to the
polemical use that the young Jew wanted to make of it.
Language speaks. It does not
so readily reveal that of which it speaks.
It cannot be a matter of daseinsanalytic indifference whether a
narrated slip was made by the narrator, or by another; in conversation, or in
private rumination; whether it was made at all, or was simulated, or invented;
and what was the human context of the factual or fictional slip; and whether it
was a ‘Freudian slip’ at all. But Daseinsanalysts have ignored not just the
human context of Freud’s ‘paradigm’ slips but the slips themselves.
Freud sought[89] a unified theory of dreams, slips, hysteria, obsessional neurosis,
paranoia, and other phenomena. So did Boss. But Freud’s theory explicitly
included jokes[90]. Boss’s did not. Slips and jokes are very close. But jokes, and
merriment, and laughter, have received little attention from Daseinsanalysts.[91]
When Tony Blair visited and thanked British troops in Iraq
on 4 January 2004 ,
he spoke of ‘weapons that can cause distraction [sic] and destruction on
a massive scale’. The Prime Minister paused briefly after saying ‘distraction’
before adding ‘and destruction’. This was televised and reported with amusement
in the press. There is a transcript on the 10 Downing Street website.[92]
Anyone who claims it was a meaningless slip is likely to be laughed at.
David Irving, towards the end of his closing speech in his libel
trial against Deborah Lipstadt in London ,
addressed the judge as ‘mein Führer’. Most people in the courtroom
started laughing, including the judge.[93]
Less well known is that, early in the trial, the judge himself made
a slip. He referred to Irving
as ‘Hitler’.[94] This
was not reported in the press or in books on the trial. If it had been noticed,
would writers have drawn conclusions as they did from Irving ’s slip? Would they have said that the
judge’s slip showed his bias? Or that it revealed his insight? Or that it meant
nothing? Without further evidence, how could one decide what, if anything, it
meant?
These examples give some idea of the meaning, indeed the high
stakes, that ordinary people see in some slips, and how they spontaneously take
account of the human context in responding to a given slip as a ‘Freudian’ one.
Often, for understandable reasons, they do not want it thought that they have
made a ‘Freudian slip’. To decide whether someone has done so, and if so, what
it may mean, may be a difficult task, as I have tried to show. Any decision
must be tentative, open to revision. This is
phenomenology. This is
Daseinsanalysis. Or it should be. But it is not the province of ‘experts’. Nor
does the maker of a slip have privileged access to its meaning or lack of
meaning.
So. Die Sprache spricht.
The study of slips is one place where Daseinsanalysis has a golden opportunity
to develop Heidegger’s insight.
4
Another place
‘on the way to language’[95]
is ‘schizophrenia’. Freud regarded slips, like dreams and jokes, as part of the
same series as ‘hysterical phobias, obsessions and delusions’.[96]
It is not necessary to believe in ‘schizophrenia’ to agree that it is not far
from the merriment of slips to the darkening of the world.
But what is
‘schizophrenia’? How do Daseinsanalysts understand it?
Bleuler, director of the Burghölzli, invented the term
‘schizophrenia’ in 1908[97].
It was a direct application of Freud’s ideas.
Bleuler had been sending his own dreams to Freud for analysis since
1905.[98]
He was chairman of the Swiss Society for Freudian Researches.[99]
He was director, with Freud, of the planned psychoanalytic yearbook of which
Jung was editor. In 1910 Bleuler published[100]
a defence of psychoanalysis in the yearbook. While using the new term
‘schizophrenia’[101]
in passing, he applied mathematical probability to justify Freud’s theory of
slips at length. He focussed in great detail on the ‘aliquis’ analysis.[102]
Bleuler remained committed to Freud’s thinking on slips. He defended
it again[103] in his
book Autistically-Undisciplined
Thinking in Medicine and How to Overcome It [my translation] (1919),
and even called in the eminent mathematician György Pólya[104]
to support his argument that Freud’s ‘aliquis’
analysis had ‘more probability value than thousands of unchallenged medical
“findings”’[105]. Freud
proudly quoted this in a 1924 footnote[106].
The 1970 English translation[107]
of Bleuler’s book unfortunately drops the chapters on probability and ‘aliquis’. His son, the psychiatrist
Manfred Bleuler, alleges[108]
they are ‘out of date’.
In his book Dementia Praecox or
The Group of Schizophrenias (1911), Bleuler says that he is undertaking
‘nothing less than the application of Freud’s ideas to dementia praecox’.[109]
The very concept of ‘schizophrenia’ is thus one of the first fruits
of Freud’s thinking.
Bleuler says the first ‘fundamental symptom’ of ‘schizophrenia’ is
‘disturbances of association’.[110]
So ‘schizophrenia’ is a ‘disease’
which manifests itself in language.
A ‘Freudian slip’ is not a disease, although Freud tries to make it
part of what he calls the ‘psychopathology’ of everyday life.
But ‘schizophrenia’, as Bleuler conceives it, has an inescapable
double aspect.
On the one hand, it refers to a person’s use of language. This is
observable. It may be misunderstood, misinterpreted, extrapolated from its
social context. But it can be accepted, assumed, in the sense of acceptio that Heidegger clarified (see
above); and it can be investigated phenomenologically, like a so-called
‘Freudian slip’, to see if it makes sense in its human context. It needs no
‘assumption’, in the sense of suppositio,
of non-human ‘forces’ ‘behind’ the phenomena.
But, on the other hand, in the concept of ‘schizophrenia’ there is
just such a causal-mechanistic ‘assumption’, or suppositio, of a hypothetical ‘disease’ which ‘causes’ the linguistic
phenomena that are regarded as its ‘symptoms’.
Daseinsanalysts, steeped in Heidegger, should be attuned to the
difference between the two kinds of assumption. Heidegger remarks that
Aristotle calls someone educated if he knows the difference. ‘If not, he is not
educated.’[111]
What light have Daseinsanalysts thrown on ‘schizophrenia’?
Boss was interested in ‘schizophrenia’. Bleuler was one of his
teachers.
In a letter to Heidegger for his eightieth birthday Boss writes of
Heidegger’s eyes[112]:
[…] the radiance of a
thinking power which was at once utterly passionate and sober and seemed to
transcend all limitations of a human intellect. Secretly and gently woven into
it was a tremendous tenderness and sensitivity of heart.
Boss says he has
met only two other men with such eyes: Freud and an Indian sage (Boss’s guru
Gobind Kaul[113] in Kashmir ). But Boss goes on to say[114]:
Already during my
student years the revered teacher and great psychiatrist Eugen Bleuler had
opened my eyes to the fact that modern natural-scientific investigations can
find no access precisely to what is properly human in our patients.
And four years
later, in his autobiographical account in Pongratz’s book Psychotherapie in Selbstdarstellung (1973), Boss speaks of four ‘men with glowing eyes’. Bleuler was ‘the first’.[115]
As a medical student, Boss had ‘hour after hour’ of ‘private seminars’ with his
ageing teacher Bleuler, who shared his ‘liking for philosophical reflection’.[116]
Boss went on to work with ‘schizophrenics’ in the sanatorium he
directed at Schloss Knonau.[117]
He corresponded with Freud about them.[118]
He wrote interesting papers on how ‘schizophrenics’ were ‘treated’[119]
and on the dreams of psychiatrists who gave them electro-shocks[120].
But neither Bleuler nor Boss disputed there was a ‘condition’,
‘schizophrenia’, which was caused by a ‘disease’, also called ‘schizophrenia’.
Bleuler, it is true, in his book on ‘autistically-undisciplined
thinking’, went so far as to say[121]:
‘The concept of mental illness (as it
is, not as it should be) is precisely not
a medical, but rather a social one.’
But what should ‘the concept of mental illness’ be? As Szasz
has been arguing[122]
for nearly fifty years, the concept is a logical category mistake.
Where did Heidegger stand on ‘schizophrenia’ and ‘mental illness’?
Heidegger showed great understanding of the language of allegedly
‘mentally ill’ writers and poets like Hölderlin, Nietzsche, Trakl, and Celan.[123]
He explored what he called the ‘site’ of these writers’ language with
extraordinary sensitivity.
Eckart Wiesenhütter
wrote[124]:
[…] Heidegger was
interested in psychiatry, especially with schizophrenics, with whom he sought
contact and conversations when this was possible for him […] Once he said frankly that he was not convinced
of the correctness of the exclusively medical interpretation of schizophrenia
as illness. Could it not even simply be a question of an ‘other’ kind of
thinking?
But Heidegger did not have the courage of his lack of conviction.[125] He did not stay with what he knew so well: language as the house of
Being, language as that which speaks. While uneasy about the ‘medical
interpretation of schizophrenia’, he took care not to contradict it, and in
fact endorsed it. To Hannah Arendt, Heidegger wrote that his son Jörg’s wife,
Dorothea, was ‘ill’; an editorial note explains that her ‘illness’ was
‘schizophrenia’.[126] Heidegger called Paul Celan, whose poetry he revered, ‘sick’.[127] In Zollikon Seminars,
Heidegger refers to Boss’s ‘Sun Man’[128]
and Binswanger’s ‘heel phobia’ girl[129] as ‘sick’. While criticising a ‘Dr M.’ for wanting a ‘technical’
psychotherapy that could produce only a ‘polished object’, Heidegger says that
what should ‘come out’ of
psychotherapy is a ‘healthier human
being’[130] (my emphasis).
There is no evidence that Heidegger questioned the right or duty of
psychiatrists to incarcerate and forcibly ‘treat’ the ‘mentally ill’. Nor did
he mention, let alone speak out against, the extermination of the ‘mentally
ill’ in the Third Reich.
Boss wrote to Heidegger[131]: ‘As Erheller
[Illuminator, Clarifier, Enlightener] of the spirit of technology you are also
the founder of an effective preventive medicine.’
Boss gave his magnum opus
the title Grundriss der Medizin.[132] And the Zollikon seminars were for doctors, as is repeatedly stated by both Boss and Heidegger, too often
to document here. Boss excluded non-medical psychotherapists and psychologists
from the seminars, although an occasional professor of philosophy was admitted.[133]. Non-medical people were not allowed to train as Daseinsanalysts,
decades after Freud and Jung had encouraged and trained non-medical analysts.[134] Heidegger went along with all this evidently without demur.
Heidegger, Boss and Condrau approach
‘schizophrenia’ in a ‘holistic’, ‘daseinsanalytic’ way; but they take it for
granted that it is an ‘illness’ that they are approaching. For example, Condrau
writes that Wyrsch,
Binswanger, and Boss talked to their ‘patient’ ‘as if s/he were healthy’. That
is to say, Condrau writes as if the so-called ‘patient’ were not healthy.[135]
While the Zollikon seminars were taking place, in the late
nineteen-fifties and early nineteen-sixties, R. D. Laing and Aaron Esterson in London were doing research
to test rigorously the ‘medical interpretation of schizophrenia’ that
Heidegger, according to Wiesenhütter, ‘once’ had the temerity to doubt. Laing and Esterson’s book Sanity, Madness and the Family (1964)[136]
contains tape-recorded excerpts from Esterson’s interviews with eleven families
of diagnosed women ‘schizophrenics’. He devised a phenomenological method of
interviewing as many subsets as possible of each family. In a sequel, The Leaves of Spring (1970)[137],
he studied one of the families in greater depth.
I shall present a short excerpt[138]
from an interview with one of these ‘schizophrenics’ and her mother. It is
conducted by Esterson in the early 1960s in the mental hospital where ‘Mary
Irwin’[139], the
21-year-old ‘patient’, has been incarcerated, ‘tranquillised’ by daily
electro-shocks, and ‘maintained’ by electro-shocks and Stelazine.
Esterson recommended listeners and readers[140]
to
bear in mind
certain of the apparent clinical features of the presumed illness: namely, the
designated irrational outbursts of anger, the ‘persecutory delusion’ that her
mother was killing her mind, the designated delusion that she was not a person,
the so-called speculative woolly thinking about the meaning of life, the
designated inability to face life’s difficulties, and the so-called lack of
insight into the so-called fact of being ill. And at the time of the session
the girl was still regarded by three of the senior psychiatrists in the
hospital as ill, and as manifesting these features among others.
DAUGHTER: When I was
coming home for weekends you said that I wasn’t well, and that I was selfish
and too full of myself, and all the rest of it.
MOTHER: Well, you were
selfish then, Mary. Or else it was that you were ill.
DAUGHTER: See.
MOTHER: Well, that’s how
it appeared to us, that you were selfish.
DAUGHTER: How was I
selfish?
MOTHER: Well, I can’t
remember now, but I do know that…
DAUGHTER: No, you see you
won’t tell me now, so I don’t know how, so if I get better again I won’t know
if I’m right or wrong, or when I’m going to crack up again or what I’m going to
do.
MOTHER: Now that’s a
form of selfishness, thrusting your opinion on me, and not listening to mine.
DAUGHTER: Well, you were
thrusting your opinion on me and not listening to mine. You see, it works both
ways.
MOTHER: I know.
DAUGHTER: But I have to
take it when I’m at home, from you, because you’re my mother. [Pause.] See, I can’t be selfish, but if
you’re selfish that’s not wrong. You’re not ill because you’re selfish, you’re
just my mother and it’s right if you can do it.
MOTHER: I know what you
mean.
ESTERSON: Well, what was
actually Mary doing when you thought she was either selfish or ill, what was
she actually doing?
MOTHER: Well, I can’t
remember –
ESTERSON: You can’t
remember –
MOTHER: – but I mean if
Mary says [inaudible] – I can
remember saying she was selfish.
ESTERSON: You can
remember? [To Mary.] Can you
remember what you were doing?
DAUGHTER: No, I can’t
remember, I can’t remember much about my whole holiday.
MOTHER: At Maureen’s?
DAUGHTER: No, before that.
MOTHER: Well we went to
Maureen’s just after you went into hospital. But I know you went back to us at
Christmas, and you never went back to the shop, to the hairdressing. And it was
more than a week after, I remember that was one of the things I thought you
were selfish in.
DAUGHTER: What was I
selfish about?
MOTHER: Well, not
letting us know anything about what you were doing or anything. And we never
knew until I rang the hospital to see how you were that you hadn’t been back to
the hairdressing.
DAUGHTER: Who was I being
selfish to? Don’t you think that maybe that I wasn’t selfish, I just didn’t,
didn’t – rely on you any more. I
wasn’t selfish at all, I was righting myself,
I was establishing myself. It wasn’t
selfishness.
As Esterson says[141]:
‘What has happened to the schizophrenia? Where is the girl’s madness?’
The mother says to the daughter: ‘[…] you
were selfish […] Or else […] you were ill.’
Mary says: ‘See.’
It is difficult to convey the poignancy with which Mary articulates
this monosyllable.
(In Sanity, Madness and the
Family, this first part of the conversation is wrongly transcribed, to read[142]:
MOTHER: Well you were selfish then
Mary. It was because you were ill.
MARY: Sick.
This destroys
the sense of this important exchange.)
A less resourceful daughter might simply give in, and be crushed.
And this daughter has been crushed.
This is why she is in the madhouse. But she is not totally crushed. And
Esterson is providing a space for her to be heard.
In this space, the daughter finds words for what she has been trying
to do. She is, she says, neither selfish nor ill. What she is trying to do is
to ‘establish’ herself. She is trying
to establish her self. She
emphasises: ‘establish myself’.
As Esterson says[143]:
[…] study the
designated schizophrenic directly in
his relevant social context in a phenomenologically and dialectically valid
manner, and to a significant extent the apparent signs and symptoms of the
presumed illness disappear like morning mist before the sun […]
Boss says something similar in his Grundriss der Medizin (1971)[144]:
[…] with no single
patient can one speak of his being schizophrenic per se. Rather, one must
always ask: schizophrenic under the excessive demands of what pattern of human
relationships?
But Boss’s language still begs the question of what ‘schizophrenic’
means. And Boss has defined the whole field of Daseinsanalysis, in the title of
his book and elsewhere, as part of medicine.
He and Heidegger constantly refer to ‘patients’ as ‘ill’. This is an
unnecessary and tragic limitation of Daseinsanalysis.[145]
From Esterson’s point of view, this isn’t a medical problem at all. The primary problem is that Mary is seen as
having a medical problem. Nor is it even a question of something non-medical wrong with Mary.
But Mary’s parents and her doctors have a linguistic problem. They do not understand what Mary is saying.
This is not because she is stupid or inarticulate. I have her school reports.
She was the best in her class at English.[146]
The psychiatrists, in particular, have a severe linguistic problem.
As Esterson says[147]:
Such was the
hypnotic effect of the prior assumption of illness, that one had constantly to
remind oneself that there was no evidence to substantiate this assumption […]
It is what Wittgenstein calls[148]
‘the Verhexung [bewitchment] of our Verstandes [intellect, reason, common
sense] by the means of our language’.[149]
Mary is struggling, as Wittgenstein says philosophy does[150],
against this serpent power. Most psychiatrists, most existential analysts and
Daseinsanalysts, most philosophers even, do not even see it.
Esterson and Laing have been misunderstood. When they are mentioned
at all, they are said to have made a questionable contribution to the
‘aetiology’ of the ‘illness’, ‘schizophrenia’. For example, van Deurzen and
Kenward write[151]:
‘Laing […] believed schizophrenia was the result of the alienating power of the
schizophrenogenic family’.
Laing and Esterson repeatedly emphasise[152]
that they are not trying to throw
light on the ‘aetiology’ of a hypothetical ‘illness’, ‘schizophrenia’. The
first reference[153]
in the first edition of their book is to Thomas Szasz, who had recently
published The Myth of Mental Illness[154]. They are questioning the existence of ‘schizophrenia’. But no one
mentions this.
They write[155]:
‘No one can deny us the right to disbelieve in the fact of schizophrenia.’ But
their disbelief in ‘schizophrenia’ is not mentioned, let alone discussed. Here
is another wonder of language: silence. We have heard many words at this Forum
about silence and meditation, but nothing about Totschweigen: how silence may kill.
Perhaps Laing and Esterson’s argument is wrong. But one cannot prove
an argument wrong if one has not mentioned what it is.
Esterson and Laing are questioning the existence of an ‘illness’,
‘schizophrenia’. And Mary is herself questioning whether she is ill. She says
she doesn’t think she has an illness at all. For the psychiatrists, this is
merely another symptom of the illness they assume she has. As we saw, she
‘lacks insight into the fact that she ill’.
Kafka might have done justice to this new Inquisition.[156]
But very few follow Szasz and Esterson in refusing to collude with it, although
many pay lip-service.
It is not enough to say, as Daseinsanalysts at this Forum have said,
that if they were ‘treating’ this young woman they would ignore her
‘diagnosis’. One can ‘ignore’ it but still believe it. Most Daseinsanalysts do
appear to believe in ‘schizophrenia’.
And even, or especially, if the Daseinsanalyst disbelieves in ‘schizophrenia’, he cannot responsibly ignore a
report, from his client or from a third party, that the client has been
diagnosed as ‘schizophrenic’. Authentic daseinsanalytic therapy may require
clarifying, and giving the client the opportunity to realise and reflect on, how
she has been confused, mystified and demoralised by her family’s and her
doctors’ treating her experience and actions as the unintelligible outcome of a
disease process. Such clarifying may require discussing with her the
‘diagnosis’ of ‘schizophrenia’ itself.
Heidegger fell into the trap of ignoring the ‘diagnosis’, despite
his great sensitivity. But he was a layman. Boss might have clarified matters
for him, but failed to do so even for himself.
Boss presents a few case vignettes[157]
from Heidegger’s Zollikon seminars and conversations with Boss as if they
displayed the golden touch of Heidegger on daseinsanalytic practice. And
indeed, in a 1965 seminar, Heidegger[158]
gives an extraordinary and fascinating response to a
1930 case study of a ‘schizophrenic’ by Franz Fischer[159].
However, Heidegger is silent on Fischer’s report[160]
of an ‘unexpected’ visit to the ‘hospitalised’ patient by his father. The patient
says[161]:
‘[…]
I don’t know you. Are you the father? […] He looks like my father, but false
and not real, perhaps made of mist or painted air, a great deception against me
[…] How long have I been here? […] Perhaps I’ve already been here longer than my
father is actually old […]’
Fischer analyses the alleged ‘disturbance’ of
‘thought’ and ‘space-time structure’ in the patient’s language, but does not
consider the possibility that the patient might be stating accurately what he
feels about his father. Fischer mentions the patient’s ‘internment’ in the
‘institution’, but not the father’s necessary role in this. He does not say how
the father relates to his son, or what he
says to him.
Heidegger, Boss[162],
Stern[163],
and Minkowski[164]
all discuss this case of Fischer’s at length, without mentioning the father, or
the son’s ‘internment’. This is the standard psychiatric tradition.[165]
Heidegger was discussing Fischer’s case in
Zollikon in 1965, one year after the publication of Sanity, Madness and the Family. Did Heidegger read Fischer’s paper
which mentions the father, or did Boss supply him only with the excerpt he
discusses? This seems almost certain, as Boss makes it clear that he supplied ‘sections’
(‘Abschnitte’)[166],
even of Freud’s writings, presumably in photocopy, rather than books, for
Heidegger to peruse.
Four decades on, have Daseinsanalysts noticed
Szasz’s work on the language of ‘mental health’, or Laing and Esterson’s work
on the language of families?
I have found no references to Szasz in daseinsanalytic writings,
although I have shown[167]
how his thinking on ‘mind’ is in tune with Heidegger’s.
Condrau mentions Laing a few times. But I have
seen no acknowledgement in daseinsanalytic writings that Laing based his
analysis of ‘false self’ in The Divided
Self on Heidegger’s ‘das Man’.[168]
Nor is Esterson’s discussion of ‘ontic security’[169]
in The Leaves of Spring mentioned,
although it is clearly based on Heidegger.
Sanity, Madness and the
Family uses Sartre’s terms ‘praxis’ and
‘process’ (‘processus’).[170]
Is this why Daseinsanalysts ignore it?[171]
Do these terms have no place in Daseinsanalysis? At stake is the distinction
between ‘motive’ and ‘causality’, moral and physical causes, that Heidegger[172]
emphasises in Zollikon Seminars.[173]
The book could be rewritten using Heidegger’s terms, and would be no more or
less daseinsanalytic.
It is already
daseinsanalytic from cover to cover.
Laing and Esterson say[174]:
‘Our findings are presented with very few interpretations, whether existential
or psychoanalytic.’ And[175]:
Our
discussion and comments on each family are pared down to what seems to us to be
an undeniable bedrock.
Inferences
about experiences that the experiencers themselves deny, and about motives and
intentions that the agent himself disavows, present difficulties of validation
that do not arise at that phenomenological level to which we have restricted
ourselves. […]
Here,
then, the reader will find documented the quite manifest contradictions that
beset these families […]
The authors do not speculate about what lies ‘behind’ the
contradictions they document. Daseinsanalysts should therefore be able to hear
language speaking in Sanity, Madness and
the Family.
Why do Daseinsanalysts have such difficulty in accepting the
phenomenological nature of ‘Freudian slips’ but such ease in accepting the
utterly unphenomenological attribution of the hypothetical suppositio of the supposed ‘disease’, ‘schizophrenia’?
Why do they not follow the logic of their position, as implied in
their rejection of Freud’s so-called ‘Grundsatz’,
and explore the territory in which Laing and Esterson are pioneers?
There seems little hope at present that this book will be understood
in its country of origin. The ‘existential analysts’ dismiss it, mistakenly, as
‘unexistential’, and even ‘deterministic’.
Sanity, Madness and the
Family insists on discovering each of the eleven
diagnosed women’s ‘behaviour’ as autonomous, the action of a human agent, praxis. This is the book’s whole point.
It is the very antithesis of determinism. For van Deurzen and Kenward to see
‘determinism’ here[176]
is as misguided as for Freud to see it in Luther’s ‘Here I stand: I can do no
other.’
But Daseinsanalysts could embrace Sanity, Madness and the Family as a great authentic work of
Daseinsanalysis. It embodies a detailed phenomenological exploration of
language in families, and a Heideggerian ‘Destruktion’
of the concept of ‘schizophrenia’, that is not found in the official literature
of Daseinsanalysis. It points beyond the crippling conception of
Daseinsanalysis as ‘medical’[177].
‘Mary Irwin’ was ‘catatonic’. But she told
Esterson[178]
that her mother would ‘just go on and on’. ‘She seemed to stop me from
thinking.’ ‘Tell you what I do, I sort of go rigid so nobody can get at me.’ So
Mary’s ‘catatonic’ behaviour was praxis.
Mary’s sister and mother told Esterson[179],
and her sister confirmed to me four decades later[180],
after Mary’s death, that Mary dropped her ‘catatonia’ overnight to be her
sister’s bridesmaid. I have a photograph of her looking excited and vivacious
at the wedding.
‘Claire Church’[181]
was a ‘chronically institutionalised’, ‘thought-disordered’, ‘paranoid
schizophrenic’[182].
She confirmed to me, four decades later[183],
Esterson’s report[184]
that her six months of discussions with him, individually and with her mother,
had enabled her to leave hospital. She told me she had pursued a satisfying
career.
Esterson wrote[185]:
Although
this type of study functions primarily to define the nature of the problem
within the family, and is, therefore, essentially only preliminary to possible
explicit therapeutic intervention, it does itself have significant therapeutic
value, since it tends to open out issues and to facilitate communication.
The therapeutic value was not limited to the
diagnosed ‘patient’. It was not a question of ‘treating’ an ‘illness’.
In so far as this was therapeutic, it was
therapy of the word by the word.
A psychotherapist is, etymologically, an
attendant on the psyche, or soul; and here it was not a question of one soul
only.
Erasmus recalls[186]
the Greek proverb cited by Plutarch and taken from Aeschylus: ‘Psuches nosouses eisin iatroi logoi.’
(‘Words are physicians to a soul diseased.’)[187]
It is clear that the proverb is a metaphor. But
the ‘clinical’ psychiatrist calls himself
the ‘iatros’ of the ‘psuche’, the ‘physician’ of the ‘psyche’,
or ‘mind’ as he now calls it. He thinks the psyche or mind is literally diseased and he is literally its doctor.
The psychiatrist has arrogated to himself the
place of the Word, of language.
In Sanity,
Madness and the Family, not psychiatry but language speaks. It is a fitting
study for Daseinsanalysts.
It has everything to do with Heidegger’s insights that ‘die Sprache spricht’; that ‘language is
the house of Being’; and that ‘the world of Dasein
is Mitwelt [with-world]’[188].
It confirms Heidegger’s saying that the call of conscience recalls
us to our situation.[189]
It shows how language can lighten or darken our situation, as
dwellers in a house, or in a madhouse, of Being.
Literature
Arendt, H. / Heidegger, M.: Briefe 1925–1975 und andere Zeugnisse
(herausgegeben von U. Ludz), Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 1999 [1998].
Baedeker, K.: Die
Schweiz nebst den angrenzenden Teilen von Oberitalien, Savoyen und Tirol:
Handbuch für Reisende (27th edition), Leipzig: Baedeker, 1897.
Barenboim,
D.: Second BBC Reith Lecture ,
Berlin , 21 April 2006 .
Baumann, G.: Erinnerungen an Paul Celan, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1992.
Beckett, S.: All That Fall: A play for radio, 1986a
[1957], in: Beckett 1986b: 169–199.
Beckett, S.: The Complete Dramatic Works, London : Faber and Faber,
1986b.
Binswanger, L.: Freuds Auffassung des Menschen im Lichte der Anthropologie,
1947a [1936], in: Binswanger 1947b: 159–189.
Binswanger, L.: Ausgewählte Vorträge
und Aufsätze, Band 1, Bern: Francke, 1947b.
Binswanger,
L.: Der Fall Ellen West, 1957a [1944–5], in: Binswanger 1957b: 57–188.
Binswanger,
L.: Schizophrenie, Pfullingen: Neske,
1957b.
Binswanger,
L.: Mein Weg zu Freud, 1957c, in: Binswanger 1957d: 37–61.
Binswanger,
L.: Der Mensch in der Psychiatrie,
Pfullingen: Neske, 1957d.
Binswanger, L.: The case of
Ellen West, 1958 [1944–5], in: May, Angel and Ellenberger 1958: 237–364.
Binswanger, L.: Freud’s
conception of man in the light of anthropology, 1963a [1936], in: Binswanger
1963b: 149–181.
Binswanger, L.: Being-in-the-World: Selected Papers of Ludwig
Binswanger Translated and with a Critical Introduction to His Existential
Psychoanalysis by Jacob Needleman, New York
and London :
Basic Books, 1963b.
Blair, A.: PM thanks UK armed forces in Basra visit, 4 January 2004 , 10 Downing Street website, http://www.pm.gov.uk/output/Page5094.asp
(retrieved 10 January 2007 ).
Bleuler,
E.: Die Prognose der Dementia praecox, in: Allgemeine
Zeitschrift für Psychiatrie und psychisch-gerichtliche Medizin, 65 (1908):
436–464.
Bleuler, E.: Die Psychanalyse Freuds:
Verteidigung und kritische Bemerkungen, in: Jahrbuch
für psychoanalytische
und psychopathologische Forschungen, 2 (1910/11):
623–730.
Bleuler, E.: Das
autistisch-undisziplinierte Denken in der Medizin und seine Überwindung, Berlin: Springer, 1927 [1919].
Bleuler, E.: Dementia Praecox or The Group of
Schizophrenias, New York : International
Universities Press, 1950 [1911].
Bleuler, E.: Autistic
Undisciplined Thinking in Medicine and How to Overcome it (translated and
edited by Dr. E. Harms) with a preface by Dr. M. Bleuler, Darien , CT :
Hafner, 1970 [1919].
Boss, M.: Sinn
und Gehalt der sexuellen Perversionen: Ein daseinsanalytischer Beitrag zur
Psychopathologie des Phänomens der Liebe, Bern: Huber, 1947.
Boss, M.: Meaning and Content of Sexual Perversions. A
Daseinsanalytic Approach to the Psychopathology of the Phenomenon of Love, New York : Grune and
Stratton, 1949 [1947].
Boss, M.: Der Traum und seine Auslegung, Bern and
Stuttgart: Huber, 1953.
Boss, M.: Einführung in die Psychosomatische Medizin,
Bern and Stuttgart: Huber, 1954.
Boss, M.: The Analysis of Dreams, London : Rider, 1957a
[1953].
Boss, M.: Psychoanalyse und Daseinsanalytik, Bern:
Huber, 1957b.
Boss, M.: Introduction à la Médicine Psychosomatique,
Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1959a [1954].
Boss, M.: Lebensangst, Schuldgefühle und
psychotherapeutische Befreiung, Bern: Huber, 1962.
Boss, M.: Psychoanalysis and Daseinsanalysis , New York :
Basic Books, 1963a [1957b].
Boss, M.: Psychosomatics and
existentialism, 1963b [1961a], in: Proceedings
of the 3rd World Congress of Psychiatry, Montreal, Canada, 4–10 June 1961,
Vol. 3, 1963: 277–280.
Boss, M.: Grundriss der Medizin: Ansätze zu einer
phänomenologischen Physiologie, Psychologie, Pathologie, Therapie und zu einer
daseinsgemässen Präventiv-Medizin in der modernen Industrie-Gesellschaft,
Bern, Stuttgart, Wien: Huber, 1971.
Boss, M.:
Medard Boß [Selbstdarstellung], 1973a, in: Pongratz 1973: 71–106.
Boss, M.: “I dreamt last night...” A New Approach to
the Revelations of Dreaming – and Its Uses in Psychotherapy, New York : Gardner
Press, 1977a [1975b].
Boss, M.:
Die notwendige Revolution im ärztlichen Denken, 1977b [1970], in: Boss, Condrau
and Hicklin 1977: 19–36.
Boss, M.: Praxis der Psychosomatik: Krankheit und
Lebensschicksal, Bern: Benteli: 1978.
Boss, M.: Existential Foundations of Medicine and
Psychology, New York and London : Aronson, 1979a [1971].
Boss, M.: Die Grundprinzipien der
Schizophrenietherapie im historische Rückblick, 1979b [1937],
in: Boss 1979i: 11–53.
Boss, M.: Alte und neue Schocktherapien und
Schocktherapeuten, 1979c [1941], in: Boss 1979i: 95–103.
Boss, M.:
Die Bedeutung der Daseinsanalyse für die Psychologie und die Psychiatrie, 1979d
[1952], in: Boss 1979i: 151–160.
Boss, M.:
Daseinsanalytische Bemerkungen zu Freuds Vorstellung des “Unbewussten”, 1979e
[1961b], in: Boss 1979i: 245–266.
Boss, M.:
Modell und Antimodell in der Psychosomatischen Medizin, 1979f [1967], in: Boss
1979i: 327–346.
Boss, M.:
Sigmund Freud und die naturwissenschaftliche Denkmethode, 1979g [1973b], in:
Boss 1979i: 387–404.
Boss, M.:
Psychotherapie und Wissenschaft, 1979h [1974], in: Boss 1979i: 423–441.
Boss, M.: Von der Psychoanalyse zur Daseinsanalyse,
Wien, München, Zürich: Europa Verlag, 1979i.
Boss, M.: Das
Unbewusste, was ist das?, 1982a [1981], in: Boss 1982b: 132–150.
Boss, M.: Von der Spannweite der Seele, Bern:
Benteli, 1982b.
Boss, M.: Indienfahrt eines Psychiaters (fourth
edition), Bern, Stuttgart, Toronto: Huber, 1987 [1959b].
Boss, M.: “Es träumte mir vergangene Nacht...”:
Sehübungen im Bereiche des Träumens und Beispiele für die praktische Anwendung
eines neuen Traumverständnisses (second edition), Bern, Göttingen, Toronto:
Huber, 1991 [1975b].
Boss, M.: Anxiety, guilt and
psychotherapeutic liberation, 1994a [1962], in: Hoeller 1994 [1990]: 71–92.
Boss, M.: The unconscious –
What is it?, 1994b [1981], in: Hoeller 1994 [1990]: 237–249.
Boss, M.,
Condrau, G. and Hicklin, A.: Leiben und
Leben: Beiträge zur Psychosomatik und Psychotherapie, Bern: Benteli, 1977.
Boss, M.
and Holzhey-Kunz, A.: Das Konzept des Widerstandes in der Daseinsanalyse, 1982
[1981], in: Boss 1982b: 111–131.
Budgen, F.: James Joyce and the Making of ‘Ulysses’ and
other writings, Oxford & New York : Oxford
University Press, 1989 [1934].
Cohn, H. W.: Authenticity and
the aims of psychotherapy, 1993, in:
Journal of the Society for Existential Analysis, 4 (1993): 48–55.
Cohn, H. W.: Misconceptions
in existential psychotherapy, 1995, in: Journal
of the Society for Existential Analysis, 6.1 (1995): 20–27.
Cohn, H. W.: Existential Thought and Therapeutic Practice,
London : Sage
Publications, 1997a.
Cohn, H. W.: Phenomenology
and psychotherapy, 1997b, in: Journal of
the Society for Existential Analysis, 8.1 (1997): 39–45.
Cohn, H. W.: John Bowlby’s
concern with the actual phenomenological aspects of attachment theory, 1998,
in: Journal of the Society for
Existential Analysis, 9.1 (1998): 43–50.
Cohn, H. W.: Heidegger and the Roots of Existential
Therapy, London , New York : Continuum, 2002.
Condrau, G.: Die Daseinsanalyse von
Medard Boss und ihre Bedeutung für die Psychiatrie, Bern: Huber, 1965a.
Condrau, G.: Psychosomatik der
Frauenheilkunde, Bern und Stuttgart: Huber, 1965b.
Condrau,
G.: Sigmund Freud und Martin Heidegger:
Daseinsanalytische Neurosenlehre und Psychotherapie, Freiburg:
Universitätsverlag / Bern, Stuttgatt, Toronto: Huber, 1992.
Condrau, G.: Letter, 1994,
in: Journal of the Society for
Existential Analysis, 5 (1994): 45–47.
Condrau, G.: Martin Heidegger’s Impact on Psychotherapy,
Dublin , New York ,
Vienna : Edition
Mosaic, 1998a.
Condrau,
G.: Daseinsanalyse:
Philosophisch-anthropologische Grundlagen; Die Bedeutung der Sprache,
Dettelbach: Röll, 1998b [1989].
Condrau, G.: Personal
communication (telephone), 2002.
Cooper, D.: Psychiatry and
Anti-Psychiatry, London :
Tavistock, 1967.
Eissler, K. R.: Letter to
Anna Freud, 21 February 1982 ,
Library of Congress, Washington ,
DC , 1982.
Erasmus, D.: Collected Works of Erasmus: Adages II vii 1
to III iii 100 (translated and annotated by R. A. B. Myers), Toronto : University
of Toronto Press , 1992.
Esterson, A.: The Leaves of Spring: A Study in the
Dialectics of Madness, London :
Tavistock, 1970.
Esterson, A.: Understanding
families: A dialectical approach, lecture to the Conference on Ethnomethodology,
Labelling and Deviance at the University
of Edinburgh , School of Criminology
and Forensic Studies, 28–30 June 1972, unpublished, 1972.
Esterson, A.: Families,
breakdown and psychiatry, 1976a, in: New
Universities Quarterly, 1976 (Summer): 285–312.
Esterson, A.: Anti-Psychiatry,
letter, 1976b, in: The New Review, 3
(November 1976, No. 32): 70–71.
Fischer,
F.: Raum-Zeit-Struktur und Denkstörung in der Schizophrenie. II, 1930, in: Zeitschrift für die gesamte Neurologie und
Psychiatrie, 124 (1930): 241–256.
Flew, A.
and Vesey, G.: Agency and Necessity,
Oxford and New York: Blackwell, 1987.
(Freud GW) Freud, S.: Gesammelte Werke, Bd. 1–18, Frankfurt am Main: S. Fischer, 1960–68.
(Freud SE) Freud, S.: The Standard
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Vols. 1–24, London : The Hogarth Press
and The Institute of Psycho-Analysis, 1953–75.
Freud, S.:
Postcard to Martha Freud from Maloja, 13 August 1898 , Library of Congress, Washington , DC ,
1898.
Freud, S.: Unser Herz zeigt nach dem
Süden: Reisebriefe 1895–1923 (herausgegeben con C. Tögel unter Mitarbeit
von M. Molnar), Berlin: Aufbau, 2002.
(Freud/Bernays): Sigmund Freud – Minna Bernays Briefwechsel 1882–1938
(herausgegeben von A. Hirschmüller), Tübingen: edition diskord, 2005.
(Freud/Jung): The Freud/Jung Letters: The Correspondence
between Sigmund Freud and C. G. Jung (edited by W. McGuire), London : The Hogarth Press
and Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1974.
Guttman, S. A.,
Parrish, S. M., Ruffing, J. and Smith, P. H., Jr.: Konkordanz to Freud GW, Waterloo , Ontario : North Waterloo Academic Press, 1995.
Gray, C.: Personal
communication, 2000.
Heaton, J. M.: Theoretical
practice: The place of theory in psychotherapy, 1976, in: Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 7.2 (May 1976):
73–85.
Heaton, J. M.: Freud and
Heidegger on the interpretation of slips of the tongue, 1982, in: Journal of the British Society for
Phenomenology, 13.2 (May 1982): 129–142.
Heaton, J. M.: The divided
self: Kierkegaard or Winnicott?, 1991, in: Journal
of the Society for Existential Analysis, 2 (1991): 30–37.
Heaton, J. M.: The self, the
divided self and the other, 1995, in: Journal
of the Society for Existential Analysis, 6.1 (1995): 31–60.
Heaton, J. M.: Conversation
with A. Stadlen, 12 May 2006.
Heidegger, M.: Being and Time (translated by J.
Macquarrie and E. Robinson), London :
SCM Press, 1962 [1927].
Heidegger, M.: Discourse on Thinking, New York : Harper and Row, 1969 [1966].
Heidegger, M.: Language,
1971a [1959a], in: Heidegger 1971b: 187–210.
Heidegger, M.: Poetry, Language, Thought, New York , Evanston , San Francisco , London :
Harper and Row, 1971b.
Heidegger,
M.: Erläuterungen zu Hölderlins Dichtung,
Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 1981 [1944].
Heidegger, M.: A dialogue on
language between a Japanese and an inquirer, 1982a [1993c], in: Heidegger 1982c
[1971c]: 1–54.
Heidegger, M.: Language in
the poem: a discussion on Georg Trakl’s poetic work, 1982b [1993b], in:
Heidegger 1982c [1971c]: 159–198.
Heidegger, M.: On the Way to Language, New York : Harper and
Row, 1982c [1971c].
Heidegger,
M.: Sein und Zeit, Tübingen:
Niemeyer, 1986 [1927].
Heidegger,
M.: Zollikoner Seminare: Protokolle –
Zwiegespräche – Briefe (herausgegeben von M. Boss), Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann, 1987.
Heidegger,
M.: Über den Humanismus, Frankfurt am
Main: Klostermann, 1991 [1947].
Heidegger, M.: Gelassenheit,
Pfullingen: Neske, 1992 [1959e].
Heidegger,
M.: Die Sprache, 1993a [1959a], in: Heidegger 1993d [1959d]: 9–33.
Heidegger,
M.: Die Sprache im Gedicht: Eine Erörterung von Georg Trakls Gedicht, 1993b
[1959b], in: Heidegger 1993d [1959d]: 35–82.
Heidegger,
M.: Aus einem Gespräch von der Sprache: Zwischen einem Japaner und einem
Fragenden, 1993c [1959c], in: Heidegger 1993d [1959d]: 83–155.
Heidegger,
M.: Unterwegs zur Sprache, Stuttgart:
Neske, 1993d [1959d].
Heidegger, M.: Being and Time (translated by J.
Stambaugh), Albany :
State University of New York Press, 1996a [1927].
Heidegger, M.: Letter on
‘humanism’, 1998a [1947], in: Heidegger 1998b: 239–276.
Heidegger, M.: Pathmarks, Cambridge :
Cambridge University Press, 1998b.
Heidegger, M.: Elucidations of Hölderlin’s Poetry, Amherst , NY :
Prometheus Books, 2000.
Heidegger, M.: Zollikon Seminars: Protocols – Conversations
– Letters (edited by M. Boss), Evanston ,
IL : Northwestern University Press,
2001a [1987].
Heidegger,
M.: Einleitung in die Philosophie (Gesamtausgabe,
Bd. 27), Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 2001b [1996b].
Hirschmüller,A.:
Sigmund Freud und Minna Bernays: Wer lag im Bett?, 20 January 2007, in: http://www.fr-online.de/in_und_ausland/kultur_und_medien/feuilleton/?em_cnt=1054877 (retrieved 21 January
2007).
Hoeller, K. (ed.): Readings in Existential Psychology and Psychiatry,
New Jersey :
Humanities Press, 1994 [1990].
(Irving v. Penguin and
Lipstadt): Transcription from the
stenographic notes of the trial in the High Court of Justice, 1996 I. No. 113,
Queen’s Bench Division, Royal Courts of Justice, Strand, London, before Mr
Justice Gray, between David John Cawdell Irving, claimant, and (1) Penguin
Books Ltd and (2) Deborah E. Lipstadt, defendants, London: Harry Counsell
& Company, 2000.
Irving, D.: Personal
communication (email), 2000.
Jaenicke, U.: Der Biss der
Muse, 2004, in: Daseinsanalyse, 20
(2004): 193–202.
Jonas, P.: Telephone
conversation with A. Stadlen, 17
June 2006 .
Joyce, J.: Ulysses, London : The Bodley Head, 1958 [1922].
Kaufmann, W.: Discovering the Mind (Volume Three): Freud
versus Adler and Jung , New York : McGraw-Hill, 1980.
Lacan, J.: Écrits,
Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1966.
Laing, R. D.: The Divided Self: An Existential Study in Sanity and Madness, London :
Tavistock, 1960.
Laing, R. D.: Series and nexus in the family, 1962, in: New Left Review, 15 (May–June 1962): 7–14.
Laing, R. D.: The Politics of Experience
and The Bird of Paradise, Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1967.
Laing, R. D. and Cooper, D.
G.: Reason and Violence: A Decade of Sartre’s Philosophy 1950—1960, London : Tavistock, 1964.
Laing, R. D. and Esterson,
A.: Sanity, Madness and the Family
(Volume 1): Families of Schizophrenics, London : Tavistock, 1964.
Laing, R. D. and Esterson, A.: Sanity,
Madness and the Family: Families of Schizophrenics (second edition),
Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1970 [1964].
Laing, R. D. and Esterson,
A.: Sanity, Madness and the Family:
Families of Schizophrenics (second edition), New York : Basic Books, 1971 [1964].
Laplanche, J.: Notes on
afterwardsness, 1999a, in: Laplanche 1999b.
Laplanche, J.: Essays on
Otherness (edited by J. Fletcher), London :
Routledge, 1999b.
Leboyer, F.: Birth Without Violence, London : Wildwood House,
1975 [1974].
Leibowitz, N.: New Studies
in Bereshit (Genesis), Jerusalem :
Eliner Library, (n.d.).
Maciejewski, F.: Der Moses des
Sigmund Freud: Ein unheimlicher Bruder, Göttingen:
Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, 2006.
Mann, T.: Joseph and His Brothers (translated by
H. T. Lowe-Porter), London :
Random House, Vintage, 1999 [1933, 1934, 1936, 1943].
Marinelli, L. and Mayer, A.: Träume nach Freud: Die
‘Traumdeutung’ und die Geschichte der psychoanalytische Bewegung, Vienna:
Turia + Kant, 2002.
May, R., Angel,
E. and Ellenberger, H. F. (ed.): Existence:
A New Dimension in Psychiatry and Psychology, New York : Basic Books, 1958.
Meerwein, F.: Psychiatrie und
Psychoanalyse in der psychiatrischen Klinik, Basel: Karger, 1965.
Meringer,
R.: Wie man sich versprechen kann, 1900, in: Neue Freie Presse, 23 August 1900
Midrash, Bereshit Rabbah: London :
Soncino Press, 1983.
Minkowski, E.: Lived Time, Evanston , IL :
Northwestern University Press, 1970 [1933].
Minkowski,
E.: Le Temps Vécu, Paris: Quadriges /
Presses Universitaires de France, 1995 [1933].
Mullan, B.: Mad to be Normal :
Conversations with R. D. Laing, London :
Free Association Books, 1995.
Nabokov, V.: Lolita, Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin,
1980 [1955].
O’Neill, S. and Gurdon, H.:
At last, Clinton
says sorry for affair, 1998, in: Daily
Telegraph, 5 September
1998 : 1.
Pongratz,
L. J.: Psychotherapie in
Selbstdarstellung, Bern: Huber, 1973.
Radday, Y. T. and Brenner,
A.: On Humour and the Comic in the Hebrew
Bible, Sheffield : Almond Press, 1990.
Reid, T.: An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the
Principles of Common Sense (edited by D. R. Brookes), Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2000 [1764].
Rice, J. L.: Comic devices in
‘The death of Ivan Ilich’, University
of Oregon , unpublished,
2000.
Roudinesco, É. and Plon, M.: Dictionnaire de la
Psychanalyse (nouvelle édition), Paris: Fayard, 2000.
Safranski, R.: Martin
Heidegger: Between Good and Evil, Cambridge ,
MA and London : Harvard University Press, 1998 [1994].
Sartre, J.-P.: L’Être et le Néant: Essai
d’Ontologie Phénoménologique (édition corrigée avec index par A. Elkaïm-Sartre),
Gallimard: n.d. [1943].
Sartre, J.-P.: Saint Genet: Comédien et Martyr, Paris:
Gallimard, 1952.
Sartre,
J.-P.: Critique de la Raison Dialectique précédé
de Question de Méthode, Paris:
Gallimard, 1960.
Sartre, J.-P.: Saint Genet: Actor and Martyr, London : W. H. Allen, 1964 [1952].
Sartre, J.-P.: Being and Nothingness, New York : Washington Square , 1966 [1943].
Sartre, J.-P.: Search for a Method, New York : Random House, Vintage, 1968
[1960].
Sartre, J.-P.: Critique of Dialectical Reason: I. Theory of Practical Ensembles, London : New Left Books,
1976 [1960].
Schiller, F.: The
Piccolomini, translated by S. T. Coleridge, 1903a [1800], in: Schiller
1903b, Vol. 3: 1–147.
Schiller, F.: Friedrich Schiller’s Works, Vols. 1–10, London: Nimmo,
1903b.
Shakespeare, W.: The
Merchant of Venice ,
1596–1597, in: Shakespeare 1951 [1623]: 223–253.
Shakespeare, W.: The
Complete Works, London and Glasgow : Collins, 1951 [1623].
Skues, R. A.: On
the dating of Freud’s aliquis slip,
2001, in: International Journal of
Psychoanalysis, 82 (2001): 1185–1204.
Skues, R. A.,
Stadlen, A. and Swales, P. J.: ‘Aliquis’:
Historical detection – existential analysis, 12-hour Freud Centenary Seminar, London : Regent’s College
Conference Centre, 24
September 2000 .
Skues, R. A., Stadlen, A. and
Tanner, T.: Unpsychopathologising everyday life, 12-hour
Inner Circle Seminar, London :
Regent’s College Conference Centre, 7 October 2001 .
Solomon, M.: Late Beethoven: Music, Thought, Imagination,
Berkeley , Los Angeles ,
London : University of California
Press, 2003.
Soncino Chumash: The Five Books of Moses with
Haphtaroth (edited by Rev.
Dr. A. Cohen), London , Jerusalem , New York :
The Soncino Press, 1983.
Stadlen, A.:
Dreaming of M. H., 1996, transcript of lecture to 3rd Forum of the International Federation of
Daseinsanalysis and 9th Conference of the Society for Existential
Analysis, London ,
unpublished, 29 September
1996 .
Stadlen, A.:
Demythologising Daseinsanalysis, 1999, lecture to 4th Forum of the International
Federation of Daseinsanalysis, Zürich,
unpublished, 7 May 1999 .
Stadlen, A.: Rezension: Martin Heidegger (edited by Medard Boss), Zollikon Seminars: Protocols – Conversations – Letters, in: Daseinsanalyse, 18 (2002): 165–170.
Stadlen, A.: Unknotting 1:
‘Just how interesting psychoanalysis really is’, 2003a, in: Arc de Cercle, 1.1 (2003): 143–176.
Stadlen, A.: Essay review:
Gion Condrau, Martin Heidegger’s Impact
on Psychotherapy, 2003b, in: Existential
Analysis, 14.1 (2003): 162–178.
Stadlen, A.: ‘A poor model
for those in training’: The case of Thomas Szasz, 2003c, in: Existential Analysis, 14.2 (2003): 213–244.
Stadlen, A.: Essay review.
Heidegger’s Zollikon Seminars: The
‘American’ translation, 2003d, in: Existential
Analysis, 14.2 (2003): 354–372.
Stadlen, A.: The
Daseinsanalysis of everyday life, 2003e, lecture to 5th Forum of the International Federation
of Daseinsanalysis, Vienna ,
unpublished, 4 October 2003 .
Stadlen,
A.: ‘Medical Daseinsanalysis’, 2005, in: Existential
Analysis, 16.1 (2005): 169–177.
Stadlen, N. and
Stadlen, A.: Families: ‘Till
this moment, I never knew myself’, 2005, in:
van Deurzen and Arnold-Baker 2005: 133–142.
Stern, P. J.: Introduction to
the English translation, 1983 [1979]), in: Boss 1979a [1971]: ix–xxii.
Stone, J. A.: Letter to New
York Times, in: PSYART Archives – December 2006, week 4 (#8), http://lists.ufl.edu/cgi-bin/wa?A2=ind0612d&L=psyart&D=0&T=0&P=883,
unpublished, dated 25
December 2006 (retrieved 10 January 2007 ).
Swales, P. J.: Freud, Minna
Bernays, and the conquest of Rome :
New light on the origins of psychoanalysis, 1982a, in: New American Review, 1 (1982): 1–23.
Swales, P. J.: Freud, Minna
Bernays, and the imitation of Christ, 1982b, typescript
of lecture delivered at The New School for Social Research, New York City , unpublished, May 20, 1982 .
Swales, P. J.: In statu
nascendi: Freud, Minna Bernays, and the creation of Herr Aliquis, 1998, transcript
of lecture for the History of Psychiatry Section, Cornell Medical Center, New
York Hospital, New York, unpublished, 7 January 1998.
Swales, P. J.: Freud, death, and sexual pleasures: On the psychical mechanism
of Dr. Sigm. Freud, 2003, in: Arc de Cercle, 1.1 (2003): 4–74.
Szasz, T. S.: The Myth of Mental Illness: Foundations of a
Theory of Personal Conduct, New
York : Hoeber, 1961.
Szasz, T. S.: The Myth of Mental Illness: Foundations of a
Theory of Personal Conduct, London :
Secker and Warburg, 1962 [1961].
Szasz, T. S.: The Manufacture of Madness: A Comparative
Study of the Inquisition and the Mental Health Movement, London : Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1971
[1970].
Szasz, T. S.: Law, Liberty ,
and Psychiatry: An Inquiry into the Social Uses of Mental Health Practices,
London :
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1974 [1963].
Szasz, T. S.: Schizophrenia: The Sacred Symbol of
Psychiatry, Oxford : Oxford University
Press, 1979a [1976].
Szasz, T. S.: The Myth of Psychotherapy: Mental Healing as
Religion, Rhetoric, and Repression, Oxford : Oxford University
Press, 1979b [1978].
Szasz, T. S.: Pharmacracy: Medicine and Politics in America , Westport ,
CT and London :
Praeger, 2001.
Timpanaro, S.: The Freudian Slip: Psychoanalysis and
Textual Criticism, London :
New Left Books, 1976 [1974].
Tolstoy, L.: The Death of Ivan Ilyich (translated by
R. Edmonds), London :
Penguin, 1995 [1886].
van Deurzen, E.: Paradox
and Passion in Psychotherapy: An Existential Approach to Therapy and Counselling,
Chichester, West Sussex :
Wiley, 1998.
van Deurzen, E. and
Arnold-Baker, C. (ed.): Existential
Perspectives on Human Issues: A Handbook for Therapeutic Practice, Basingstoke , Hampshire: Palgrave, 2005.
van Deurzen, E. and Kenward,
R.: Dictionary of Existential
Psychotherapy and Counselling, London :
Sage, 2005.
Wittgenstein, L.: Philosophical Investigations, Oxford : Blackwell, 1958
[1953].
Appendix:
Citations of the sentence that Binswanger called Freud’s ‘Grundsatz’
No.
|
Year
|
Author
|
Paper or chapter
|
Book or journal
|
Page
|
1
|
1947a [1936]
|
Binswanger, L.
|
Freuds Auffassung des Menschen im
Lichte der Anthropologie
|
Ausgewählte Vorträge und Aufsätze, Band 1
|
165
|
1t
|
1963a [1936]
|
Binswanger, L.
|
Freud’s conception of man in the light of anthropology
|
Being-in-the-World (ed.
Needleman, J.)
|
156
|
2
|
1957a [1944–5]
|
Binswanger, L.
|
Der Fall Ellen West
|
Schizophrenie
|
142, 150
|
2t
|
1958 [1944–5]
|
Binswanger, L.
|
The case of Ellen West
|
Existence: A
New Dimension in Psychiatry and Psychology (ed. May, R., Angel, E. and Ellenberger,
H. F.)
|
319, 327
|
3
|
1947
|
Boss, M.
|
Sinn und Gehalt
der sexuellen Perversionen (First edition, repeated in
second, third, fourth editions)
|
14
|
|
3t
|
1949 [1947]
|
Boss, M.
|
Meaning and
Content of Sexual Perversions
|
11
|
|
4
|
1979d [1952]
|
Boss, M.
|
Die Bedeutung der Daseinsanalyse für
die Psychologie und die Psychiatrie
|
Von der Psychoanalyse zur Daseinsanalyse
|
152
|
5
|
1953
|
Boss, M.
|
Der
Traum und seine Auslegung
|
28
|
|
5t
|
1957a [1953]
|
Boss, M.
|
The Analysis
of Dreams
|
29
|
|
6
|
1954
|
Boss, M.
|
Einführung in die psychosomatische Medizin
|
16
|
|
6t
|
1959a [1954]
|
Boss, M.
|
Introduction à la Médicine Psychosomatique
|
7
|
|
7
|
1957c
|
Binswanger, L.
|
Mein Weg zu Freud
|
Der Mensch in der Psychiatrie
|
42
|
8
|
1957b
|
Boss, M.
|
Psychoanalyse
und Daseinsanalytik
|
100, 130
|
|
8t
|
1963a [1957b]
|
Boss, M.
|
Psychoanalysis
and Daseinsanalysis
|
102–103
|
|
9
|
1963b [1961a]
|
Boss, M.
|
Psychosomatics and Existentialism
|
Proceedings of
the 3rd World Congress of Psychiatry,
|
278
|
10
|
1962
|
Boss, M.
|
Lebensangst, Schuldgefühle und psychotherapeutische Befreiung
|
18
|
|
10t
|
1994a [1962]
|
Boss, M.
|
Anxiety, guilt and psychotherapeutic liberation
|
73
|
|
11
|
1987
|
Heidegger, M.: (ed. Boss, M.)
|
Seminar vom 24.und 28. Januar 1964;
Zwiegespräch mit Medard Boss, 29. Januar 1964
|
Zollikoner Seminare (Herausgegeben
von Medard Boss)
|
6, 7, 233
|
11t
|
2001a [1987]
|
Heidegger, M.: (ed. Boss, M.)
|
Seminar of 24 and 28 January 1964; conversation with Medard
Boss,
|
Zollikon
Seminars (edited by Medard Boss)
|
5, 7, 186
|
12
|
1965a
|
Condrau, G.
|
Die Daseinsanalyse von Medard Boss und ihre Bedeutung für die Psychiatrie
|
14–15
|
|
13
|
1965b
|
Condrau, G.
|
Psychosomatik
der Frauenheilkunde
|
63
|
|
14
|
1979f [1967]
|
Boss, M.
|
Modell und Antimodell in der
psychosomatischen Medizin
|
Von der Psychoanalyse zur Daseinsanalyse
|
332–333
|
15
|
1977b [1970]
|
Boss, M.
|
Die notwendige Revolution im
ärztlichen Denken
|
Leiben und Leben: Beiträge zur Psychosomatik und Psychotherapie (Herausgegeben von Medard Boss, Gion Condrau und Alois
Hicklin)
|
24
|
16
|
1971
|
Boss, M.
|
Grundriss der
Medizin
|
185
|
|
16t
|
1979a [1971]
|
Boss, M.
|
Existential
Foundations of Medicine and Psychology
|
57
|
|
17
|
1973a
|
Boss, M.
|
Medard Boß [Selbstdarstellung]
|
Psychotherapie in Selbstdarstellungen (Herausgegeben von Ludwig J. Pongratz)
|
88
|
18
|
1979g [1973b]
|
Boss, M.
|
Sigmund Freud und die
naturwissenschaftliche Denkmethode
|
Von der Psychoanalyse zur Daseinsanalyse
|
391
|
19
|
1979h [1974]
|
Boss, M.
|
Psychotherapie und Wissenschaft
|
Von der Psychoanalyse zur Daseinsanalyse
|
424
|
20
|
1991 [1975b]
|
Boss, M.
|
“Es träumte mir vergangene Nacht...” (Second edition)
|
191
|
|
20t
|
1977a [1975b]
|
Boss, M.
|
“I dreamt last
night...”
|
168
|
|
21
|
1978
|
Boss, M.
|
Praxis der Psychosomatik: Krankheit und Lebensschicksal
|
204
|
|
22
|
1982 [1981]
|
Boss, M. and Holzhey-Kunz, A.
|
Das Konzept des Widerstandes in der
Daseinsanalyse
|
Von der Spannweite der Seele (by M.
Boss)
|
112
|
23
|
1992
|
Condrau, G.
|
Sigmund Freud und Martin Heidegger
|
11, 18
|
|
24
|
1993
|
Cohn, H. W.
|
Authenticity and the aims of psychotherapy
|
Journal of the
Society for Existential Analysis, 4
|
53
|
25
|
1995
|
Cohn, H. W.
|
Misconceptions in existential psychotherapy
|
Journal of the
Society for Existential Analysis, 6.1
|
23
|
26
|
1997a
|
Cohn, H. W.
|
Existential
Thought and Therapeutic Practice
|
22
|
|
27
|
1997b
|
Cohn, H. W.
|
Phenomenology and psychotherapy
|
Journal of the
Society for Existential Analysis,
8.1
|
39
|
28
|
1998
|
Cohn, H. W.
|
John Bowlby’s concern with the actual phenomenological aspects
of attachment theory
|
Journal of the
Society for Existential Analysis,
9.1
|
45
|
29
|
2002
|
Cohn, H. W.
|
Heidegger and
the Roots of Existential Therapy
|
73–74
|
For full bibliographical details see Literature.
Key:
[ ] = date of first edition,
original language edition, or original lecture or document.
t = translation.
Author’s address:
‘Oakleigh’, 2A Alexandra Avenue , GB – London N22 7XE (stadlen@aol.com)
I
thank Ms Angela Buxton, the late Prof. Dr. med. et phil. Gion Condrau, the late
Dr Aaron Esterson, Mr Justice Charles Gray, Dr John M. Heaton, Mr David Irving,
Sir Peter Jonas, Dr. Hansjörg Reck, Dr Richard A. Skues, Mrs Naomi Stadlen, Ms
Rachel Stadlen, Mr Peter J. Swales and Professor Thomas S. Szasz for their kind
assistance and criticism.
[1] Genesis 1: 3. (Soncino Chumash.)
[2] ‘Die
Sprache ist das Haus des Seins’ (Heidegger 1991
[1947]: 5; 1998a [1947]: 239).
[3] In ‘A dialogue on language between a
Japanese and an inquirer’, Heidegger (1993c [1959c]: 90, 111–118; 1982a
[1993c]: 5, 21–28) said he had ‘made shift’ by describing language as ‘the
house of Being’.
[4] Genesis 3: 1. (Soncino Chumash.)
[5] Ibid. 2: 16–17.
[6] Ibid. 3: 2–3.
[7] See Midrash, Bereshit Rabbah,
XIX, 3; and Leibowitz (n.d.: 25).
[8] This was noticed by Benno Jacob, cited by Leibowitz (n.d.: 31).
[9] See Radday and Brenner (1990: 64, 84–86) for a discussion of the
humour of this Biblical narrative.
[10] Genesis 14: 21. (Soncino Chumash.)
[11] Ibid.14: 22–23.
[12] I do not know any Biblical commentator who mentions that these are,
respectively, the first two-way conversation and the first two-way human
conversation in the Bible.
[13] Stadlen 1999.
[14] Stadlen 2003e.
[15] Heidegger 1993a [1959a]: 12; 1971a [1959a]: 190.
[16] Barenboim 2006.
[17] Leboyer 1975 [1974]: 10–13.
[18] Heidegger 2001b [1996b]: 125.
[19] Stadlen 1999; 2003e.
[20] Stadlen 2003a: 163–166, n. 77.
[21] Freud GW 11: 62; SE 15: 67.
[22] Binswanger 1947a [1936]: 165; 1963
[1936]: 156.
[23] Binswanger 1957a [1944–5]: 142; 1958
[1944–5]: 319.
[24] For the profusion of citations of Freud’s
so-called ‘Grundsatz’ by these
authors, see the Appendix to the present paper. (For an earlier version see
Stadlen 2003a: 174–176.)
[25] Heidegger 1987: 6; 2001a [1987]: 5.
[26] Freud GW
4: 179; SE 6: 162; my
translation.
[27] Guttman et al. 1995.
[28] Ibid.
[29] Freud GW 4: 60, n. 1; SE 6: 51, n. 2.
[30] Walter Kaufmann (1980: 24) translates Freud’s ‘Fehlleistung’ as ‘mischievement’. This brings out the ‘mischievous’, ‘trickster’
nature of such ‘slips’ or ‘parapraxes’.
[31] See Stadlen 2003a: 163–166, n. 77.
[32] Heaton in his article ‘Freud and Heidegger
on the interpretation of slips of the tongue’ (1982) points out that ‘Freudian
slips’ (and jokes) illustrate Heidegger’s dictum, ‘language speaks’. Heaton
does not refer to anything Heidegger actually wrote on interpreting slips of
the tongue, but in effect speculates, quite convincingly, on what Heidegger
might have said had he, at that time, published something on slips.
[33] Stadlen 2003a: 163–166, n. 77; 2003d:
359–360.
[34] Jonas 2006.
[35] PORTIA: One half of me is yours, the other half yours –
Mine own, I would say; but if mine, then yours,
And so all yours.
(Shakespeare, The Merchant of
Venice, Act III, Scene 2, 1951 [1596–1597]: 238, cited in Freud GW 4: 108; SE 6: 97–98.)
[36] QUESTENBERG: What now? Where go you then?
OCTAVIO: To her herself.
QUESTENBERG:
To –
OCTAVIO: [Interrupting him and correcting himself.] To the Duke. Come let us go –
(Schiller, The Piccolomini, Act I, Scene 5,
Coleridge’s translation, 1903a [1800]: 31–32, cited in Freud GW 4: 107; SE 6: 96–97.)
[37] Rice (2000: 17) writes that, at the end of Tolstoy’s story ‘The
Death of Ivan Ilich’ (Tolstoy 1995 [1886]: 88; Rice’s translation),
Ivan Ilich intends to say ‘Forgive me’ to his son and wife at his
deathbed (Prosti) but instead he says
‘Let me pass’ (Propusti). Our latter-day
understanding of the psychopathology of everyday life behoves us to pay rather
more attention to this slip of the tongue, and to the result more than the
intent. Instead of the most profound human utterance, imploring a depth of
response healing for both parties (‘Forgive me’), the dying man issues a
peremptory official order that discourages compassion and clears the way for
his exit (‘Let me pass’).
The point of the slip, evident in Rice’s account, is lost in the
standard English translations of the story, including the Rosemary Edmonds one
cited above.
[38] —Well, that’s a
point, says Bloom, for the wife’s admirers.
—Whose admirers? says Joe.
—The wife’s advisers, I mean, says Bloom.
—Whose admirers? says Joe.
—The wife’s advisers, I mean, says Bloom.
Then he starts all confused mucking it up […]
(Joyce, Ulysses, 1958
[1922]: 297.) This slip is noticed by Budgen (1989 [1934]: 162). It is recalled
in the ‘Circe’ episode of Ulysses
(Joyce, Ibid.: 428):
BLOOM: […] Frankly, though she
had her advisers or admirers, I never cared for her style […]
[39] ‘Ah, how long!’ lamented the butler.
‘Ah, how short!’ cried the baker – but at
once gave another frightful start and assured them that he also had meant to
say how long.
(Mann, Joseph and His Brothers,
1999 [1943]: 887.) This is one of a series of slips by Pharaoh’s baker in the
chapters ‘The two fine gentlemen’ and ‘Of the stinging worm’ (Ibid.: 878–897).
[40] MRS ROONEY: No, Mr Rooney, Mr Tyler I mean, I am tired of light old hands on my shoulders and other senseless places, sick and tired of them.
(Beckett, All That Fall,
1986a [1957]: 175.)
And:
MRS
ROONEY: [Exploding.]
Will you get along now, Mr Rooney, Mr Tyler I mean, will you get along with you
now and cease molesting me?
(Ibid.:
176.)
[41] [Humbert Humbert transcribes from a book, Who’s Who in the Limelight:]
Quine, Dolores. Born in 1882, in Dayton , Ohio .
Made New York
debut in 1904 in Never Talk to Strangers.
Has disappeared since in [a list of some thirty plays follows.]
(Nabokov,
Lolita, 1980 [1955]: 32.)
[42] Heidegger 1987: 233; 2001a [1987]: 186–187.
[43] Freud GW
1:511, 512; SE 3: 281; GW 2/3: 211; SE 4: 205; GW 10: 243; SE 14: 270; GW 12: 72, n. 1; 88; SE
17: 45, n. 1; 58; Lacan 1966: 256, 684, 839; Laplanche 1999a.
[44] Freud GW 15: 86; SE 22: 80;
my translation.
[45] Heidegger 1987: 357; 2001a [1987]: 287;
my translation.
[46] Boss 1963a [1957b]: 92.
[47] Meerwein 1965: 37.
[48] Boss 1979f [1967]: 333.
[49] Boss 1982a [1981]:144; 1994b [1981]: 245.
[50] Freud GW 4: 282–283; SE 6: 253–254.
[51] Flew and Vesey 1987: 65.
[52] Heaton 1976: 76.
[53] Boss 1982a [1981]: 149; 1994b [1981]: 248.
[54] Heidegger 1992 [1959e]: 23–26; 1969 [1966]: 54–57. See also Stadlen
1996.
[55] Condrau 1998b [1989]: 178.
[56] Ibid.: 177.
[57] Condrau 1994: 46.
[58] ‘Oder
gibt es am Ende in Wirklichkeit gar keine Traumsymbole?’ (Boss 1953: 97; 1957a [1953]: 90; my translation).
[59] Solomon 2003: 42.
[60] Ibid.: 43.
[61] Ibid.: 45.
[62] O’Neill and Gurdon 1998.
[63] Stadlen 1996; 1999; 2003e.
[64] Jaenicke 2004.
[65] Freud GW
4: 67; SE 6: 59; GW 11: 28; SE 15: 35; GW 17: 144–145; SE 23: 284.
[66] Freud GW
4: 67; SE 6: 59.
[67] Meringer 1900.
[68] Freud SE 6: 59; my
modification of Strachey’s translation.
[69] Boss 1963a [1957b]: 97; 1971: 346–347;
1979e [1961]: 259–260; 1979a [1971]: 139; 1982a [1981]: 143–144; 1994b [1981]:
244; Condrau 1998b [1989]: 176–177.
[70] Boss and Holzhey-Kunz 1982 [1981]: 111. (‘Die Daseinsanalyse
will selber nichts anderes sein als eine geläuterte Psychoanalyse.’)
[71] Sartre n.d. [1943]: 185–206; 1966 [1943]:
211–237 (Part 2, Chapter 2, III).
[72] Freud GW
4: 5–12; SE 6: 1–7.
[73] Freud GW
4: 13–20; SE 6: 8–14.
[74] Freud GW
4: 20; SE 6: 14.
[75] Swales 1982a,b; 1998; 2003; Skues 2001; Skues, Stadlen and Swales 2000; Skues, Stadlen
and Tanner 2001.
[76] Freud GW 4: 17–18; SE 6:
11 –12.
[77] Eissler 1982. In this unpublished letter to Anna Freud, Eissler
drafts a letter for Miss Freud to send to Peter Swales. It reads, in part:
Dear Mr Swales
As I am told you claim (spread the rumor) that the aliquis
parapraxis had referred to my father although he wrote expressis verbis that it
concerned “a person other than myself”[.] You may try to justify your claim by
reference to my father’s 1899 paper & thus would show the lack of ability
to distinguish between the permissable [sic]
and the impermissable [sic], the
decent & indecent […] I shall not support
the research of a person who claims that my father was a liar, nor shall I
continue a correspondence with him.
Truly
Freud’s 1899 paper is ‘Screen memories’ (GW 1: 529–554; SE 3:
299–322). It purports to discuss a patient of Freud’s but is now agreed by
scholars to be (thinly) disguised autobiography. Swales never received such a
letter from Miss Freud.
[78] For a deduction of an ‘is’ from an ‘ought’ to rival Eissler’s see
Hirschmüller 2007.
[79] For example, Roudinesco and Plon write (2000: 505) that Freud ‘remained
all his life a faithful spouse, capable of forbidding himself any sexual
transgression’ (‘resta toute sa vie un époux fidèle, capable de s’interdire
toute transgression sexuelle’). They do not say how they know this.
[80] Freud 1898; 2002: 109. A photocopy of the postcard (Freud 1898)
from the Freud Archives in the Library of Congress, Washington, DC, shows that
there is a line break between ‘Schweizer’ and ‘Haus’, and that the ‘H’ of ‘Haus’
may be upper or lower case, so that it is unclear whether Freud is writing
‘Schweizer Haus’ or ‘Schweizerhaus’. Either of these could be either a proper
name or a general description. Freud’s phrase ‘in einem bescheidenen Schweizer Haus [or Schweizerhaus]’ obscures the fact that
‘Schweizerhaus’ was the name of one, and only one, hotel in Maloja – and
not a ‘modest’ one.
[81] Maciejewski 2006: 138, n. 124; 146.
[82] Baedeker 1897: 377. The Schweizerhaus (Hôtel Osteria vecchia) is
one of only two hotels in Maloja given an asterisk of recommendation by
Baedeker that year (the year before Freud’s stay there with Minna).
[83] Maciejewski’s discovery that Freud and Minna booked into a hotel
room as man and wife does not prove that they had sexual intercourse there and
then. It does not disprove Swales’s earlier hypothesis (Swales 1982b: 25–29; 2003: 40–41), based on, among other things, a careful reading
of Freud’s ‘three fates’ dream (GW 2/3: 210–214; SE 4: 204–208),
that Freud did not consummate a sexual relationship with Minna until two years
later. It does not prove that they ever had a sexual relationship. But
it does make it even odder to claim to know that they never did.
[84] Freud GW
6: 127; SE 8: 115.
[85] It is to be regretted that the New York
Times did not publish a letter to the editor (Stone 2006) from the
psychoanalyst Professor Jennifer Arlene Stone Ph. D. (not an invention of Nabokov’s) which
advised:
In Europe, the correct
and polite grammatical form of address for any woman over 30 years old, whether
married or not, is Frau (German), Signora (Italian), Madame (French). […] All
that these articles and claims reveal is how unanalyzed Freud’s detractors are:
they fail to realize that their display of curiosity about the primal Oedipal
scenario is nothing but their uncomfortable fantasies about their parental own.
Professor Stone’s
guidance as to ‘the correct and polite grammatical form of address’ was,
unfortunately, not available to Freud when, on holiday with his wife in 1898,
less than a month after sharing a room with his 33-year-old sister-in-law in
Maloja, he sent Minna a postcard from Ragusa dated 7 September and one from
Spalato dated 9 September, addressing both cards to ‘Fräulein Minna Bernays’ (Freud/Bernays 2005:
248). What the correct form of address has to do with Freud’s guestbook description
of Minna as his ‘Frau’ (‘wife’) will no doubt be apparent to the
adequately ‘analyzed’.
[86] Timpanaro 1976 [1974]: 30–40.
[87] Virgil Aeneid IV 625.
[88] Timpanaro 1976 [1974]: 35.
[89] Freud GW
2/3: VII; SE 4: xxiii.
[90] Freud GW 6; SE 8.
[91] The words ‘Witz’, ‘Humor’, ‘joke’, ‘humour’ do not occur in
the indexes of the principal works of Boss and Condrau on the relation between
Daseinsanalysis and psychoanalysis (Boss 1963a [1957b]; 1971; 1979a [1971];
Condrau 1992; 1998b [1989]). Nor can I find them in Boss 1957b, which has only
a name index.
[92] Blair 2004.: ‘PM thanks UK armed
forces in Basra
visit’.
[93] I was in the courtroom and witnessed this
event. The official trial transcript reads (Irving v. Penguin and
Lipstadt, Day 32, 15 March 2000: 193):
[MR IRVING:] I am
clearly seen to interrupt my speech, shake my head at them and gesticulate with
my left hand to them to stop, and I am clearly heard to say, “You must not”,
because they are shouting the “Siegheil” slogans, Mein Fuhrer, and things like,
“you must not always be thinking of the past”.
[94] The
transcript reads (Irving
v. Penguin & Lipstadt, Day 7, 20 January 2000:
42):
MR JUSTICE GRAY: Professor Watt, when you said what you have just said about Hitler
(sic) as a military historian, you are talking…
MR IRVING: Irving .
I am indebted to Mr David Irving for pointing this out
to me (Irving 2000).
[95] Heidegger 1993d [1959d]; 1982c [1971c].
[96] Freud GW
2/3: VII; SE 4: xxiii.
[97] Bleuler 1908: 436.
[98] Marinelli and Mayer 2002: 144–159.
[99] Freud/Jung 1974: 89, n. 1.
[100] Bleuler 1910/11.
[101] Ibid.: 688.
[102] Ibid.: 648–654.
[103] Bleuler 1927 [1919]: 128–133, 151–154.
[104] Ibid.: 157–160.
[105] Ibid.: 154 (my
translation).
[106] Freud GW
4: 17, n. 1; SE 6: 11–12, n. 1.
[107] Bleuler 1970 [1919].
[108] Ibid.: xix.
[109] Bleuler 1950 [1911]: 1.
[110] Ibid.: 14.
[111] Heidegger 1987: 6, 234; 2001a [1987]: 6, 187.
[112] Heidegger 1987: 363–364; 2001a [1987]: 293–294; my translation.
[113] Boss 1987 [1959b]: Abb. 12, 13.
[114] Heidegger 1987: 364; 2001a [1987]: 294; my translation.
[115] Boss 1973a: 79; my translation.
[116] Ibid.: 80.
[117] Ibid.: 85.
[118] Ibid.: 86.
[119] Boss 1979b [1937].
[120] Boss 1979c [1941].
[121] Bleuler 1927 [1919]: 59; 1970 [1919]: 73; his emphasis, my
translation. See Szasz 1979a [1976]: 27–32 for a discussion of Bleuler’s book.
[122] E.g., Szasz 1961; 2001.
[123] Heidegger 1981 [1944]; 2000 [1981]; 1993a
[1959a]; 1993b [1959b]; 1971a [1959a]; 1982b [1993b]. See Stadlen 2003b:
173–174.
[124] Wiesenhütter
1979: 158; my translation.
[125] See Stadlen 2003b; 2005; Stadlen and Stadlen 2005.
[126] Arendt/Heidegger 1999 [1998]: 132–133, 296.
[127] Safranski 1998: 423; Baumann 1992: 80.
[128] Heidegger 1987: 196; 2001a [1987]: 152.
[129] Heidegger 1987: 256; 2001a [1987]: 206.
[130] Heidegger 1987: 270; 2001a [1987]: 215.
[131] Heidegger 1987: 368–369; 2001a [1987]: 297.
[132] Boss 1971.
[133] Condrau 2002.
[134] Ibid.
[135] Condrau 1998a: 94.
[136] Laing and Esterson 1964.
[137] Esterson 1970.
[138] See Esterson 1972; 1976a. The excerpt I played is part (Esterson
1972: 12–13; 1976a: 298–299) of a longer excerpt (Esterson 1972: 11–15; 1976a:
297–301) played by Esterson during a lecture, ‘Understanding families: A
dialectical approach’ (Esterson 1972). I give my own transcription from the
original tape, as there are some minor inaccuracies in the transcription in
Esterson (1972; 1976a).
[139] Laing and Esterson 1964: 189–208 (Family 9: The Irwins).
[140] Esterson 1976a: 296–297.
[141] Ibid.: 301.
[142] Laing and Esterson 1964: 205.
[143] Esterson 1976a: 302.
[144] Boss 1971: 506; 1979a [1971]: 236; my translation.
[145] See Stadlen 2005.
[146] I am grateful to the sister of the late ‘Mary Irwin’ for her help with
my research.
[147] Esterson 1976a: 296.
[148] Wittgenstein 1958 [1953]: 47 (I.
109).
[149] Cooper (1967: 1–2) uses Wittgenstein’s aphorism to describe Szasz’s
view of ‘schizophrenia’. But Cooper himself accepts ‘schizophrenia’ as ‘not an
entirely meaningless term’ for a certain kind of ‘micro-social crisis
situation’.
[150] Wittgenstein (loc. cit.,
my translation): ‘Philosophy is a struggle [ein
Kampf] against the bewitchment of our intellect by the means of our
language.’
[151] van Deurzen and Kenward 2005: 118.
[152] See Preface to Second Edition, Laing and Esterson 1971 [1964]:
vii–x.
[153] Laing and Esterson 1964: 4, n. 1. This footnote refers to The Myth
of Mental Illness (Szasz 1961; 1962 [1961]). The corresponding footnote in
the Pelican edition (Laing and Esterson 1970 [1964]: 18, n.) refers
specifically to ‘p. 16n etc.’ of Szasz’s book. But p. 16 contains no footnote;
indeed, it is blank. Nor does any other footnote in Szasz’s book develop the
argument to which Laing and Esterson allude, namely, that a person should be presumed
healthy until proved otherwise. Almost certainly, ‘p. 16n’ is a misprint for
‘p. 100’. It is on p. 100 that Szasz argues for the presumption of health, as
Szasz himself points out in his next book, Law,
Liberty and Psychiatry (1974 [1963]: 224).
[154] Szasz 1961; 1962 [1961].
[155] Laing and Esterson 1971 [1964]: vii.
[156] See Szasz 1971 [1970].
[157] E.g. Heidegger 1987:
195–196; 2001a [1987]: 151–152.
[158] Heidegger 1987: 66–70; 2001a [1987]:
51–54.
[159] Fischer 1930.
[160] Ibid.: 249–252.
[161] Ibid.: 249–250; my translation.
[162] Boss 1971: 492–496; 1979a [1971]:
228–231.
[163] Stern 1979: xix–xx.
[164] Minkowski 1995 [1933]: 269–270; 1970
[1933]: 288–289.
[165] See also Stadlen and Stadlen (2005: 134–138) for a further
examination in its historical context of Heidegger’s Zollikon discussion of
Fischer’s case.
[166] Boss 1973a: 96.
[167] Stadlen 2003c: 222–225.
[168] Mullan 1995: 152. This statement by Laing refutes Heaton’s (1991:
32–33) assertion that Laing’s The Divided
Self (1960) was ‘greatly influenced’ by ‘Winnicott’s notion of a true and
false self’.
[169] Esterson 1970: 30–32, 53, 96, 129, 149.
[170] Laing and Esterson 1964: 8.
[171] Heaton (1995: 34) writes that Sanity,
Madness and the Family is a ‘very good read’ but that ‘its dependence on
Sartre’s theory is disastrous’. But, in conversation with me, Dr John Heaton
(2006) agreed that its findings are, in fact, independent of Sartre’s theory.
He agreed that, while he was objecting to some of the book’s language, it could
be rewritten in Heideggerian terms – or, as he suggested, in terms of Thomas
Reid’s (2000 [1764]) ‘common sense’ philosophy – without altering the point it
is making. However, since Heaton (1995: 34) writes that the book is making a
‘valuable point’ about the ‘manifestations of schizophrenia’, it is not clear
whether Heaton has registered that the primary purpose of Laing and Esterson’s
book is to question the existence of
‘schizophrenia’.
[172] Heidegger writes (1987: 28; 2001a [1987]:
23; my translation and brackets): ‘Motiv
ist ein Beweggrund für menschliches Handeln; Kausalität: Beweggrund für
Abfolgen innerhalb des Naturprozesses.’ (‘Motive is
a ground for human action; causality: ground for sequences within the process
of nature.’)
[173] Sartre (1960: 533–549, 673–688, 704–736; 1976 [1960]: 539–559,
716–734, 754–794) uses ‘processus’ (‘process’) to refer to human (not
natural) events. Laing and Esterson (1964: 8) define the term, somewhat
misleadingly, to mean ‘a continuous series of operations that have [sic]
no agent as their author’. They then use it to include both what
Heidegger calls ‘the process of nature’ and what Sartre means by ‘processus’,
namely, human (usually group) events which appear (before dialectical
investigation) to have no author.
[174] Laing and Esterson 1964: 11.
In practice, Laing’s ideas were dominated by a psychoanalytic
thinking which limited the extent of his existential thought, for his overall
conceptualisation of his patients was deterministic.
This is the opposite of the truth. Laing made a fundamental contribution
to the non-deterministic theory and practice of psychoanalysis. His
existential-phenomenological psychoanalytic thinking, far from ‘limit[ing] the
extent of his existential thought’, served and extended his existential thought.
Laing rejected determinism, clinicism and ‘pseudo-irreducibles’. He
sought help from Sartre’s anti-determinist philosophy (Sartre 1952; 1957 [1936–1937]; 1960; 1964 [1952]; 1966 [1943]; 1968 [1960];
1976 [1960]; 2000 [1943]; Laing and Cooper 1964; Laing and Esterson 1964;
Stadlen and Stadlen 2005: 134–138; Scott and
Thorpe 2006). His central project was to show that many human events which
psychiatrists and others had seen as just happening, presumably the outcome of
deterministic causality, were intelligible or comprehensible as the outcome of
personal agency. In Sartrean terms, Laing’s project was to reveal process
as the outcome of praxis.
The first reference in the first edition of Laing and Esterson’s
book Sanity, Madness and the Family (1964: 4, n. 1) is to Szasz’s
The Myth of Mental Illness (1961),
written against determinism in psychoanalysis and psychiatry.
Moreover, in Sanity, Madness and the Family, Laing and
Esterson (1964: 11) explicitly and deliberately refrain from
psychoanalytic interpretation.
When Laing does draw on psychoanalysis, elsewhere, it is always in
an existential-phenomenological way.
For example, he writes in The Politics of Experience (1967:
30) about so-called ‘defence mechanisms’ in psychoanalysis:
There is thus some phenomenological validity in
referring to such ‘defences’ by the term ‘mechanism’. But we must not stop
there. They have this mechanical quality, because the person as he experiences
himself is dissociated from them. He appears to himself and to others to suffer
from them. They seem to be processes he undergoes, and as such he experiences
himself as a patient, with a particular psychopathology.
But this is so only from the perspective of his own
alienated experience. As he becomes de[-]alienated he is able first of all to
become aware of them, if he has not already done so, and then to take the
second, even more crucial, step of progressively realizing that these are
things he does or has done to himself. Process becomes converted back to
praxis, the patient becomes an agent.
Ultimately it is possible to regain the ground that
has been lost. These defence mechanisms are actions taken by the person on his
own experience. On top of this he has dissociated himself from his own action.
The end-product of this twofold violence is a person who no longer experiences
himself fully as a person, but as a part of a person, invaded by destructive
psychopathological ‘mechanisms’ in the face of which he is a relatively
helpless victim.
Laing’s argument here is in accord with an observation of Sartre’s
in Critique de la Raison Dialectique
(1960: 117, n. 1; 1976 [1960]: 17, n. 6; my translation) that
The single fact that Anna Freud (after so many others) can define
these functions as ‘mechanisms of defence’ stamps the work of the ego with
an a priori inertia.
Laing writes in Interpersonal Perception (1966: 15):
Projection is a form of action directed at one’s own experience of
the other. It is called a ‘mental mechanism’. This is a very misleading term,
since it is neither mental nor mechanical. It is an action whose intentional
object is one’s own experience of the other. It is to the credit of
psychoanalysis that it has brought to light actions of this kind.
Laing’s account in The Politics of Experience (1967: 29) of
what he calls transpersonal ‘defences’ is also explicitly
non-deterministic:
How she behaves toward him influences (without by any means totally
determining) how he experiences her. And his experience of her contributes to
his way of behaving towards her which in turn…etc.
Laing continues to describe ‘defence mechanisms’ and transpersonal
defences in terms of personal agency in The
Politics of the Family (1969: 26–31). He
clarifies the issue of personal agency as follows (1969: 27–28):
The operations on experience we are discussing, are commonly not
experienced themselves. So seldom does one ever catch oneself in the act, that
I would have been tempted to regard them as themselves, essentially not
elements of experience, had I not occasionally been able to catch a glimpse of
them in action myself, and had not others reported the same to me. It is
comparatively easy to catch someone else in the act.
And (1969: 29):
The operations I have alluded to are operations on one’s own
experience. They are done by one person to himself or herself. But they would
be unnecessary unless the rules of the family required them: and ineffectual
unless others cooperate.
Laing writes in The Politics of Experience (1967: 70) of a
confused family situation:
Such processes seem to have a dynamism divorced from the
individuals. But in this and every other case this process is a form of
alienation, intelligible when, and only when, the steps in the vicissitudes of
its alienation from each and every person can be retraced back to what at each
and every moment is their only origin: the experience and actions of each and
every single person.
Hence, as he writes in ‘Series and
nexus in the family’ (Laing 1962: 13):
Family pathology is an even more corrupt concept than individual psycho-pathology.
It simply extends the unintelligibility of individual behaviour to the
unintelligibility of the group.
Laing and Esterson (1964: 9) repeat these sentences in modified form
in Sanity, Madness and the Family, replacing ‘corrupt’ with
‘confused’.
Laing emphasises in Reason and Violence (Laing and Cooper
1964: 155; Laing’s translation and italics) Sartre’s remark in Critique de
la Raison Dialectique (1960: 544) about theorists of ‘group process’:
[…] they have only chosen to see and study it on the level of
its full unintelligibility.
Sartre’s original sentence (1960: 544) is:
[…] ils n’ont choisi de ne voir que lui et
de l’étudier au niveau de son inintelligibilité plénière.
Laing’s enthusiasm for this sentence is such that he italicises his
(correct) translation of it, while the (later) official English translation
misconstrues Sartre’s strong negative as a double negative and so interpolates
a ‘not’ which makes nonsense of the sentence by inverting its meaning (Sartre
1976 [1960]: 552):
[…] they have not [sic] chosen to see only it and
to study it at the level of its complete unintelligibility.
In a book, Mad to be Normal, of tape-recorded discussions
during the last two years of his life, 1988–1989,
Laing explains (Mullan 1995: 309):
[…] Adorno’s critique of existentialism made me very cautious
about using a word like ‘authentic’ any more, or his critique of immediacy made
me very chary about calling myself a phenomenologist in the Husserlian sense […]
But in these discussions Laing still (Mullan 1995: 365–366) praises Sartre for ‘cover[ing] the ground that
Freud covered’ but without ‘objectifying and translating the existalia [sic]
of the person into a meta-psychology of energy dynamics’ or ‘us[ing] a
meta-psychology to account for how you can lie to yourself and other people’.
And Laing still (Mullan 1995: 314), when asked for his
‘model’ of ‘man’, gives the existential definition:
We are creatures, as has been said, whose being is in question to
ourselves. […] we are our own question mark.
He still (Mullan 1995: 379) insists:
I’m not talking about the
aetiology of schizophrenia, I’ve always said that. I’m talking about the experience and behaviour that leads
someone to be diagnosed as schizophrenic is more socially intelligible than has
come to be supposed by most psychiatrists and most people. That is a very
embarrassing statement and people can’t hear that, and so it means that it is
translated into saying that families cause schizophrenia […]
Laing concludes (Mullan 1995: 380):
Anything you can’t put in a journal headline in a couple of
sentences that a bird mind can grasp is completely lost and collapsed into one
of these formulas; that it’s caused by genetics, or it’s caused by society. I
mean how ridiculous […]
So much for Laing’s ‘determinism’. The above examples are typical.
Many more could be given. The philosophy of personal agency and non-determinism
informs all Laing’s work.
As the sociologists Susie Scott and Charles Thorpe write in their
recent paper, ‘The sociological imagination of R. D. Laing’ (Scott and Thorpe 2006:
334):
Social determinism, like biological determinism, treats human
behavior as a ‘process’, being driven by impersonal forces operating on a
different level to or behind the backs of actors. Instead, Laing treats
schizophrenic behavior as praxis, that is, in terms of what agents are
doing.
There is a legitimate criticism to be made of Laing’s equivocation about
‘mental illness’ (Szasz 1976a; 1979 [1976b]: 45–83; 1984: 42–45; 2004: 116–117;
2005; Esterson 1976; Stadlen 1979). But van Deurzen and Kenward do not make it.
Their comment that he was ‘deterministic’ is
without foundation. This is a matter of fact, not of emphasis, opinion,
or interpretation. (See also Stadlen 2007: 133–136).
It is important to realise that, despite their opening words, ‘In
practice…’, van Deurzen and Kenward are claiming to describe Laing’s ‘conceptualisation’.
The present paper has documented what Laing consistently, over many years, said
his conceptualisation was. To substantiate their claim, van Deurzen and Kenward
would have to show either that Laing was lying or that, in addition to his
explicitly stated conceptualisation documented above, he had a radically
opposed conceptualisation of which he was ‘unconscious’ but to which they had
access.
Samuel Johnson in his great dictionary (1755) defined a
‘lexicographer’ as:
A writer of dictionaries; a harmless drudge, that busies himself in
tracing the original, and detailing the signification of words.
Van Deurzen and Kenward do not appear to have busied themselves in
tracing the original, and detailing the signification of Laing’s words. Yet
reading his words is far from drudgery.
When lexicography distorts, it is not harmless. It may do great
harm.
Laing introduced existential
thinking to psychotherapy in the United Kingdom . It is regrettable
that so few existential psychotherapists and Daseinsanalysts today, including those who write in
this Journal, read what he wrote. It is to be hoped that van Deurzen and
Kenward will revise their entry for the second edition of their Dictionary.
[179] Ibid.: 201–203.
[180] Interview with ‘Angela’, sister of ‘Mary Irwin’, 1 August 2001 .
[181] Laing and Esterson 1964: 61–94.
[182] Ibid.: 61; Esterson
1976b.
[183] Interview with ‘Claire Church’, 3 January 2001 .
[184] Esterson 1976b.
[185] Esterson 1976a: 294–295.
[186] Erasmus 1992: 223–224.
[187] See Szasz 1979b [1978]: 29, 208.
[188] Heidegger 1986 [1927]: 118; 1962 [1927]:
155; 1996a [1927]: 112; my translation and brackets.
[189] Heidegger 1986 [1927]: 295–301; 1962
[1927]: 341–348; 1996a [1927]: 272–277.
No comments:
Post a Comment